Misplaced Pages

Two New Sciences: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 22:11, 8 October 2013 editChris55 (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Rollbackers9,463 edits The Law of falling bodies: an experimentally proved fact← Previous edit Revision as of 22:19, 9 October 2013 edit undoChris55 (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, Rollbackers9,463 edits The flow of time: refsNext edit →
Line 44: Line 44:


===The flow of time=== ===The flow of time===
*The ] mechanism described above was engineered to provide ] of the water during the experiments, thus providing a constant flow of water for the durations of the experiments, and embodying what Newton called ''duration''. In particular, Galileo ensured that the vat of water was large enough to provide a uniform jet of water. The ] mechanism described above was engineered to provide ] of the water during the experiments, thus providing a constant flow of water for the durations of the experiments, and embodying what Newton called ''duration''. In particular, Galileo ensured that the vat of water was large enough to provide a uniform jet of water.
*Galileo's experimental setup to measure the literal '']'' (]), in order to describe the motion of a ball, was palpable enough and persuasive enough to found the sciences of mechanics and kinematics. ], in particular, could be founded on the notion of the linear flow of time.


*The ] was discovered by Galileo in 1599. But in the 20th century some authorities challenged the reality of Galileo's experiments, in particular the French ] ]. The experiments reported in ''Two New Sciences'' to determine the law of acceleration of falling bodies, for instance, required accurate measurements of time, which appeared to be impossible with the technology of 1600. According to Koyré, the law was arrived at deductively, and the experiments were merely illustrative thought experiments. Galileo's experimental setup to measure the literal '']'' (]), in order to describe the motion of a ball, was palpable enough and persuasive enough to found the sciences of mechanics and kinematics. ], in particular, could be founded on the notion of the linear flow of time.
The ] was discovered by Galileo in 1599. But in the 20th century some authorities challenged the reality of Galileo's experiments, in particular the French ] ]. The experiments reported in ''Two New Sciences'' to determine the law of acceleration of falling bodies, for instance, required accurate measurements of time, which appeared to be impossible with the technology of 1600. According to Koyré, the law was arrived at deductively, and the experiments were merely illustrative thought experiments.

**Later research, however, has validated the experiments. The experiments on falling bodies (actually rolling balls) were replicated using the methods described by Galileo (Settle, 1961), and the precision of the results was consistent with Galileo's report. Later research into Galileo's unpublished working papers from 1604 clearly showed the reality of the experiments and even indicated the particular results that led to the time-squared law (Drake, 1973).<ref>] (1973). "Galileo's Discovery of the Law of Free Fall". '']'' v. '''228''', #5, pp. 84-92.</ref>
Later research, however, has validated the experiments. The experiments on falling bodies (actually rolling balls) were replicated using the methods described by Galileo,<ref>
{{cite journal|title=An experiment in the history of science|first=Thomas B.|last=Settle|year=1961|journal=Science|at=Vol 133 no 3445 pages=19-23}}
</ref>and the precision of the results was consistent with Galileo's report. Later research into Galileo's unpublished working papers from 1604 clearly showed the reality of the experiments and even indicated the particular results that led to the time-squared law).<ref>
{{cite journal|authorlink=]|year=1973|title=Galileo's Discovery of the Law of Free Fall|journal=]'' |at=v. 228''', #5, pp. 84-92}}</ref>


==Notes== ==Notes==

Revision as of 22:19, 9 October 2013

Galileo Galilei: Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche intorno à due nuove scienze (1638)

The Discourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Relating to Two New Sciences (Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche, intorno à due nuove scienze, 1638) was Galileo's final book and a sort of scientific testament covering much of his work in physics over the preceding thirty years.

After his Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, the Roman Inquisition had banned publication of any work by Galileo, including any he might write in the future. After the failure of attempts to publish Two New Sciences' in France, Germany, or Poland, it was picked up by Lodewijk Elzevir in Leiden, The Netherlands, where the writ of the Inquisition was of little account (see House of Elzevir).

The same three men as in the Dialogue carry on the discussion, but they have changed. Simplicio, in particular, is no longer the stubborn and rather dense Aristotelian; to some extent he represents the thinking of Galileo's early years, as Sagredo represents his middle period. Salviati remains the spokesman for Galileo.

The Science of materials

The sciences named in the title are the strength of materials and the motion of objects. Galileo worked on an additional section on the force of percussion, but was not able to complete it to his own satisfaction.

The discussion begins with a demonstration of the reasons that a large structure proportioned in exactly the same way as a smaller one must necessarily be weaker known as the square-cube law. Later in the discussion this principle is applied to the thickness required of the bones of a large animal, possibly the first quantitative result in biology, anticipating J.B.S. Haldane's seminal work On Being the Right Size, and other essays, edited by John Maynard Smith.

The Law of falling bodies

Galileo expresses clearly for the first time the constant acceleration of a falling body which he was able to measure accurately by slowing it down using an inclined plane.

In Two New Sciences Galileo (Salviati speaks for him) used a wood molding, "12 cubits long, half a cubit wide and three finger-breadths thick" as a ramp with a straight, smooth, polished groove to study rolling balls ("a hard, smooth and very round bronze ball"). He lined the groove with "parchment, also smooth and polished as possible". He inclined the ramp at various angles, effectively slowing down the acceleration enough so that he could measure the elapsed time. He would let the ball roll a known distance down the ramp, and used a water clock to measure the time taken to move the known distance; this clock was

a large vessel of water placed in an elevated position; to the bottom of this vessel was soldered a pipe of small diameter giving a thin jet of water, which we collected in a small glass during the time of each descent, whether for the whole length of the channel or for a part of its length; the water thus collected was weighed, after each descent, on a very accurate balance; the differences and ratios of these weights gave us the differences and ratios of the times, and this with such accuracy that although the operation was repeated many, many times, there was no appreciable discrepancy in the results.

Infinity

Main article: Galileo's paradox

The book also contains a discussion of infinity. Galileo considers the example of numbers and their squares. He starts by noting that:

it cannot be denied that there are as many as there are numbers because every number is a root of some square: 1 ↔ 1, 2 ↔ 4, 3 ↔ 9, 4 ↔ 16, and so on.

(In modern language, there is a bijection between the elements of the set of positive integers N and the set of squares S, and S is a proper subset of density zero). But he notes what appears to be a contradiction:

Yet at the outset we said there are many more numbers than squares, since the larger portion of them are not squares. Not only so, but the proportionate number of squares diminishes as we pass to larger numbers.

He resolves the contradiction by denying the possibility of comparing infinite numbers (and of comparing infinite and finite numbers):

We can only infer that the totality of all numbers is infinite, that the number of squares is infinite, and that the number of their roots is infinite; neither is the number of squares less than the totality of all numbers, nor the latter greater than the former; and finally the attributes "equal," greater," and "less," are not applicable to infinite, but only to finite, quantities.

This conclusion, that ascribing sizes to infinite sets should be ruled impossible, owing to the contradictory results obtained from these two ostensibly natural ways of attempting to do so, is certainly a consistent resolution to the problem but less powerful than that used nowadays. In contemporary mathematics, the problem is resolved instead by only considering Galileo's first definition of what it means for sets to have equal sizes; that is, the ability to put them in to one-to-one correspondence. This turns out to yield a way of comparing the sizes of infinite sets that is free from contradictory results.

These issues of infinity arise from problems of rolling circles: if two concentric circles of different radius roll along lines, then if the larger does not slip, it appears clear that the smaller must slip. But in what way? Galileo attempts to clarify the matter by considering hexagons, and then extending to rolling 100 000-gons, or n-gons, where he shows that a finite number of finite slips occur on the inner shape. Eventually he concludes that "The line traversed by the larger circle consists then of an infinite number of points which completely fill it; while that which is traced by the smaller circle consists of an infinite number of points which leave empty spaces and only partly fill the line", which would not be considered satisfactory now.

Reactions by commentators

"So great a contribution to physics was Two New Sciences that scholars have long maintained that the book anticipated Isaac Newton's laws of motion."--Stephen Hawking.
"Galileo ... is the father of modern physics—indeed of modern science"—Albert Einstein.

Part of Two New Sciences was actually ground breaking pure mathematics, as has been pointed out by the mathematician Alfred Renyi, who argued that it was the most significant book on mathematics in over 2000 years: Greek mathematics did not deal with motion, and so they never formulated mathematical laws of motion, even though Archimedes developed differentiation and integration. Two New Sciences opened the way to treating physics mathematically by treating motion mathematically for the first time. The Greek mathematician Zeno had designed his paradoxes to prove that motion could not be treated mathematically, and that any attempt to do so would lead to paradoxes. (He regarded this as an inevitable limitation of mathematics.) Aristotle reinforced this belief, saying that mathematic could only deal with abstract objects that were immutable. Galileo used the very methods of the Greeks to show that motion could indeed be treated mathematically. His great insight was to separate out the paradoxes of the infinite from Zeno's paradoxes. He did this in several steps. First, he showed that the infinite sequence S of the squares 1, 4, 9, 16, ...contained as many elements as the sequence N of all positive integers. See the Infinity section.This is now referred to as Galileo's paradox. Then he showed, using Greek style geometry, that a short line interval contained as many points as a longer interval. At some point he formulates the general principle that a smaller infinite set can have just as many points as a larger infinite set containing it. It was then clear that Zeno's paradoxes on motion resulted entirely from this paradoxical behavior of infinite quantities. Having removed this 2000 year old stumbling block, Galileo went on to introduce his mathematical laws of motion, anticipating Newton, as Hawking and Einstein said.

The flow of time

The water clock mechanism described above was engineered to provide laminar flow of the water during the experiments, thus providing a constant flow of water for the durations of the experiments, and embodying what Newton called duration. In particular, Galileo ensured that the vat of water was large enough to provide a uniform jet of water.

Galileo's experimental setup to measure the literal flow of time (see above), in order to describe the motion of a ball, was palpable enough and persuasive enough to found the sciences of mechanics and kinematics. Time in physics, in particular, could be founded on the notion of the linear flow of time.

The law of falling bodies was discovered by Galileo in 1599. But in the 20th century some authorities challenged the reality of Galileo's experiments, in particular the French historian of science Alexandre Koyré. The experiments reported in Two New Sciences to determine the law of acceleration of falling bodies, for instance, required accurate measurements of time, which appeared to be impossible with the technology of 1600. According to Koyré, the law was arrived at deductively, and the experiments were merely illustrative thought experiments.

Later research, however, has validated the experiments. The experiments on falling bodies (actually rolling balls) were replicated using the methods described by Galileo,and the precision of the results was consistent with Galileo's report. Later research into Galileo's unpublished working papers from 1604 clearly showed the reality of the experiments and even indicated the particular results that led to the time-squared law).

Notes

  1. (Drake 1978, p. 367). See Galileo affair for further details.
  2. "The foundation of mechanics". The Independent. Jul 6, 1914. Retrieved July 28, 2012.
  3. Galileo 1638 Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche, intorno à due nuove scienze 213, Leida, Appresso gli Elsevirii (Leiden: Louis Elsevier), or Mathematical discourses and demonstrations, relating to Two New Sciences, English translation by Henry Crew and Alfonso de Salvio 1914. Section 213 is reprinted on pages 534-535 of On the Shoulders of Giants: The Great Works of Physics and Astronomy (works by Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, Newton, and Einstein). Stephen Hawking, ed. 2002 ISBN 0-7624-1348-4
  4. Stephen Hawking, ed. p. 397, On the Shoulders of Giants.
  5. Stephen Hawking, ed. p. 398, On the Shoulders of Giants.
  6. Alfred Renyi, Dialogs on Mathematics, Holden-Day, San Francisco, 1967.
  7. Settle, Thomas B. (1961). "An experiment in the history of science". Science. Vol 133 no 3445 pages=19-23. {{cite journal}}: Missing pipe in: |at= (help)
  8. "Galileo's Discovery of the Law of Free Fall". Scientific American. v. 228, #5, pp. 84-92. 1973. {{cite journal}}: Italic or bold markup not allowed in: |journal= (help)

References

  • Drake, Stillman, translator (1974). Two New Sciences, University of Wisconsin Press, 1974. ISBN 0-299-06404-2. A new translation including sections on centers of gravity and the force of percussion.
  • Henry Crew and Alfonso de Salvio, translators, (1954). Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences, Dover Publications Inc., New York, NY. ISBN 486-60099-8. The classic source in English, originally published by McMillan (1914).
  • Titles of the first editions taken from Leonard C. Bruno 1989, The Landmarks of Science: from the Collections of the Library of Congress. ISBN 0-8160-2137-6 Q125.B87
  • Galileo Galilei, Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche intorno a due nuove scienze attinenti la meccanica e i movimenti locali (pag.664, of Claudio Pierini) pubblication Cierre, Simeoni Arti Grafiche, Verona, 2011, ISBN 9788895351049.

External links

Galileo Galilei
Scientific career
Works
Family
Related
In popular culture
Categories:
Two New Sciences: Difference between revisions Add topic