Revision as of 20:38, 14 March 2009 edit173.67.254.207 (talk) i just find it so amazingly amusing that people are more interested in Wiki standards (which change) than the proof itself← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 09:46, 2 November 2024 edit undoKku (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users115,685 editsm link syllogism | ||
(741 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{short description|Philosophical views that question the possibility of knowledge or certainty}} | |||
], one of the most famous skeptics in Western philosophy]] | |||
{{For|a more general discussion of skepticism|Skepticism}} | |||
{{Use American English|date=April 2021}} | |||
'''Philosophical skepticism''' (from ] ''σκέψις'' - ''skepsis'' meaning "enquiry" - UK and traditional spelling, | |||
{{Use mdy dates|date=April 2021}} | |||
'''scepticism''') is both a ] school of thought and a method that crosses disciplines and cultures. Many skeptics critically examine the meaning systems of their times, and this examination often results in a position of ambiguity or doubt. This skepticism can range from disbelief in contemporary philosophical solutions, to ], to rejecting the reality of the external world. One kind of ] refers to the critical analysis of claims lacking empirical evidence. We are all skeptical of some things, especially since doubt and opposition are not always clearly distinguished. Philosophical skepticism, however, is an old movement with many variations, and contrasts with the view that at least one thing is certain, but if by being certain we mean absolute or unconditional certainty, then it is doubtful if it is rational to claim to be certain about anything. Indeed, for Hellenistic philosophers claiming that at least one thing is certain makes one a dogmatist. | |||
{{Epistemology sidebar}} | |||
'''Philosophical skepticism''' (]: '''scepticism'''; from ] σκέψις ''skepsis'', "inquiry") is a family of ] views that question the possibility of ].<ref name="SEP Skepticism">{{cite web |title=Skepticism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism/ |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=12 July 2020}}</ref><ref name="SEP Certainty">{{cite web |title=Certainty |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/certainty/ |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=12 July 2020}}</ref> It differs from other forms of skepticism in that it even rejects very plausible knowledge claims that belong to basic ]. Philosophical skeptics are often classified into two general categories: Those who ], and those who advocate for the ] due to the inadequacy of evidence.<ref name=":0" /> This distinction is modeled after the differences between the ] and the ] in ]. Pyrrhonian skepticism is a practice of suspending judgement, and skepticism in this sense is understood as a way of life that helps the practitioner achieve ]. Some types of philosophical skepticism reject all forms of knowledge while others limit this rejection to certain fields, for example, knowledge about ] doctrines or about the external world. Some theorists criticize philosophical skepticism based on the claim that it is a ] since its proponents seem to claim to ''know'' that there is no knowledge. Other objections focus on its implausibility and distance from regular life. | |||
== History of skepticism == | |||
=== Ancient Western Skepticism ===<!-- This section is linked from ] --> | |||
The ] tradition of systematic skepticism goes back at least as far as ] of ]. He was troubled by the disputes that could be found within all philosophical schools of his day. According to a later account of his life, he became overwhelmed by his inability to determine rationally which school was correct. Upon admitting this to himself, he finally achieved the inner peace that he had been seeking. | |||
==Overview== | |||
From a ] point of view, Pyrrho found peace by admitting to ignorance and seeming to abandon the criterion by which knowledge is gained. Pyrrho's ignorance was not the ignorance of children or farm animals: it was a '']'', arrived at through the application of logical reasoning and exposition of its inadequacy. The school of thought developed primarily in opposition to what was seen as the ], or ultimately unfounded assertions of the Stoics; ] made distinctions between "being" and "appearing" and between the identity and the sensing of a phenomenon. | |||
{{More citations needed section|date=July 2020}} | |||
Philosophical skepticism is a doubtful attitude toward commonly accepted ] claims. It is an important form of ]. Skepticism in general is a questioning attitude toward all kinds of knowledge claims. In this wide sense, it is quite common in everyday life: many people are ordinary skeptics about ] or about ] because they doubt the claims made by proponents of these fields.<ref name="Goldstick1983"/> But the same people are not skeptical about other knowledge claims like the ones found in regular school books. Philosophical skepticism differs from ordinary skepticism in that it even rejects knowledge claims that belong to basic ] and seem to be very certain.<ref name="Goldstick1983"/> For this reason, it is sometimes referred to as ''radical doubt''.<ref name="Hansson2017">{{cite journal |last1=Hansson |first1=Sven Ove |title=The Uses and Misuses of Philosophical Scepticism: Editorial |journal=Theoria |date=September 2017 |volume=83 |issue=3 |pages=169–174 |doi=10.1111/theo.12123}}</ref> In some cases, it is even proclaimed that one does not know that "I have two hands" or that "the sun will come out tomorrow".<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Olsson |first1=Erik J. |title=Not Giving the Skeptic a Hearing: "Pragmatism and Radical Doubt" |journal=Philosophy and Phenomenological Research |date=2005 |volume=70 |issue=1 |pages=98–126 |doi=10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00507.x |jstor=40040781 |issn=0031-8205}}</ref><ref name="Comesaña2001"/> In this regard, philosophical skepticism is not a position commonly adopted by regular people in everyday life.<ref name="DeRose1999"/><ref name="Popkin"/> This denial of knowledge is usually associated with the demand that one should suspend one's ]s about the doubted ]. This means that one should neither believe nor disbelieve it but keep an open mind without committing oneself one way or the other.<ref name="Stroud1984a"/> Philosophical skepticism is often based on the idea that no matter how certain one is about a given belief, one could still be wrong about it.<ref name="Cohen1996">{{cite book |last1=Cohen |first1=Stewart |editor1-last=Craig |editor1-first=Edward |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=1996 |publisher=Routledge |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/BEAREO |chapter=}}</ref><ref name="Comesaña2001">{{cite web |last1=Comesaña |first1=Juan |last2=Klein |first2=Peter |title=Skepticism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=24 August 2022 |date=2019}}</ref> From this observation, it is argued that the belief does not amount to knowledge. Philosophical skepticism follows from the consideration that this might be the case for most or all beliefs.<ref name="Stroud1984b">{{cite book |last1=Stroud |first1=Barry |last2=Stroud |first2=Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry |title=The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism |date=5 July 1984 |publisher=OUP Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-824761-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yrHmCwAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=II Philosophical Scepticism and Everyday Life}}</ref> Because of its wide-ranging consequences, it is of central interest to theories of knowledge since it questions their very foundations.<ref name="Stroud1984a"/> | |||
According to some definitions, philosophical skepticism is not just the rejection of some forms of commonly accepted knowledge but the rejection of all forms of knowledge.<ref name="Goldstick1983">{{cite journal |last1=Goldstick |first1=D. |title=Four Forms of Philosophical Scepticism |journal=University of Toronto Quarterly |date=1 May 1983 |volume=52 |issue=3 |pages=235–240 |doi=10.3138/utq.52.3.235|s2cid=170733016 }}</ref><ref name="Stroud1984a"/><ref name="Hinton1989">{{cite journal |last1=Hinton |first1=J. M. |title=Scepticism: Philosophical and Everyday |journal=Philosophy |date=1989 |volume=64 |issue=248 |pages=219–243 |doi=10.1017/S0031819100044491 |jstor=3751409 |s2cid=144250265 |issn=0031-8191}}</ref> In this regard, we may have relatively secure beliefs in some cases but these beliefs never amount to knowledge. Weaker forms of philosophical skepticism restrict this rejection to specific fields, like the ] or ] doctrines. In some cases, knowledge per se is not rejected but it is still denied that one can ever be absolutely certain.<ref name="Popkin"/><ref name="Greco2009"/> | |||
Pyrrho and his school were not actually "skeptics" in the later sense of the word. They had the goal of ''αταραξια'' ('']'' - peace of mind), and pitted one dogmatic philosophy against the next to undermine belief in the whole philosophic enterprise. The idea was to produce in the student a state of aversion towards what the Pyrrhonists considered arbitrary and inconsequential babble. Since no one can observe or otherwise experience causation, external world (its "externality"), ultimate purpose of the universe or life, justice, divinity, soul, etc., they declared no need to believe in such things. The Pyrrhonists pointed out that, despite claims that such notions were necessary, some people "ignorant" of them get by just fine before learning about them. They further noted that science does not require belief and that faith in intelligible realities is different from pragmatic convention for the sake of experiment. For each intuitive notion (e.g. the existence of an external world), the Pyrrhonists cited a contrary opinion to negate it. They added that consensus indicates neither truth nor even probability. For example, the earth is round, and it would remain so even if everyone believed it were flat. Unless, of course, it is flat, and we all simply believe it is round. | |||
There are only few defenders of philosophical skepticism in the strong sense.<ref name="Goldstick1983"/> In this regard, it is much more commonly used as a theoretical tool to test theories.<ref name="Hansson2017"/><ref name="Goldstick1983"/><ref name="Stroud1984b"/><ref name="LeMorvan2011"/> On this view, it is a ] that can be utilized to probe a theory to find its weak points, either to expose it or to modify it in order to arrive at a better version of it.<ref name="Hansson2017"/> However, some theorists distinguish philosophical skepticism from ] in that philosophical skepticism is an approach that questions the possibility of ] in knowledge, whereas methodological skepticism is an approach that subjects all knowledge claims to scrutiny with the goal of sorting out true from false claims.{{cn|date=September 2022}} Similarly, ] differs from philosophical skepticism in that scientific skepticism is an epistemological position in which one questions the veracity of claims lacking ]. In practice, the term most commonly references the examination of claims and theories that appear to be ], rather than the routine discussions and challenges among scientists.<ref>Merton, R. K. (1942). "The Normative Structure of Science". in Merton, Robert King (1973). ''The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations''. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. {{ISBN|978-0-226-52091-9}}.</ref> | |||
The goal of this critique, which Pyrrho's followers realized would ultimately subvert even their own method, was to cultivate a distrust of all grand talk. They expected philosophy to collapse into itself. How far in this direction the Pyrrhonean commitment extended is a matter of debate. The Pyrrhonists confessed a belief in appearances, e.g. in hot and cold, grief and joy. It is impossible to deny, they admitted, that one '''seems''' to be in pain or '''seems''' to touch a piece of wood. Their world, thus, was completely ]. An accomplished Pyrrhonist could, ideally, live as well as a dogmatist but with the added benefit of not worrying about truth and falsity, right and wrong, God's will, and so forth. | |||
In ], skepticism was seen not just as a theory about the existence of knowledge but as a way of life. This outlook is motivated by the idea that suspending one's judgment on all kinds of issues brings with it ] and thereby contributes to the skeptic's ].<ref name="Greco2009"/><ref>{{cite web |last1=Vogt |first1=Katja |title=Ancient Skepticism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism-ancient/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=30 August 2022 |date=2021}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Reed |first1=Baron |title=Skepticism as a Way of Life |date=11 December 2018 |publisher=Brill |isbn=978-90-04-39353-0 |url=https://brill.com/view/book/edcoll/9789004393530/BP000005.xml |language=en}}</ref> | |||
Later thinkers took up Pyrrho's approach and extended it into modern skepticism. In the process, a split appeared within the movement, never too large or well-liked among the literati to begin with. In the ''New or Middle Academy'', ] (c. 315-241 B.C.) and ] (c. 213-129 B.C.) argued from Stoic premises that the Stoics were actually committed to denying the possibility of knowledge, but seemed to maintain nothing themselves, but ], a student of Carneades, interpreted his teacher's philosophy as suggesting an early ] account of knowledge. The Roman politician and philosopher, Cicero, also seems to have been a supporter of the probabilistic position attributed to the Middle Academy, even if the return to a more dogmatic orientation of that school was already beginning to take place. | |||
=== Classification === | |||
In the centuries to come, the words ''Academician'' and ''Pyrrhonist'' would often be used to mean generally ''skeptic'', often ignoring historical changes and distinctions between denial of knowledge and avoidance of belief, between degree of belief and absolute belief, and between possibility and probability. {{Fact|date=February 2007}} | |||
Skepticism can be classified according to its scope. ] involves being skeptical about particular areas of knowledge (e.g. ], skepticism about the external world, or skepticism about other minds), whereas ] claims that one cannot know anything—including that one cannot know about knowing anything. | |||
Skepticism can also be classified according to its method. ] has two basic approaches to skepticism.<ref>{{cite book |last = Williams|first = Michael |title = Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology|publisher = Oxford University Press|year = 2001|chapter = Chapter 5: Agrippa's Trilemma |page= 61| isbn=978-0-19-289256-0}}</ref> ]—named somewhat misleadingly after ], who was not a skeptic but used some traditional skeptical arguments in his ] to help establish his ] approach to knowledge—attempts to show that any proposed knowledge claim can be doubted. ] focuses on justification rather than the possibility of doubt. According to this view, none of the ways in which one might attempt to justify a claim are adequate. One can justify a claim based on other claims, but this leads to an ] of justifications. One can use a ]tic assertion, but this is not a justification. One can use ], but this fails to justify the conclusion. | |||
==== Sextus Empiricus ==== | |||
===Skeptical scenarios=== | |||
] (c. A.D. 200), the main authority for Pyrrhonian skepticism, worked outside the Academy, which by his time had ceased to be a skeptical or probabilistic school, and argued in a different direction, incorporating aspects of ] into the basis for evaluating knowledge, but without the insistence on experience as the absolute standard of it. Sextus' empiricism was limited to the "absolute minimum" already mentioned — that there seem to be appearances. He developed this basic thought of Pyrrho's into lengthy ]s, most of them directed against Stoics and Epicureans, but also the Academic skeptics. The common anti-skeptical argument is that if one knows nothing, one cannot know that one knows nothing, and so may know something after all. It is worth noting that such argument only succeeds against the complete denial of the possibility of knowledge. Considering dogmatic the claims both to know and not to know, Sextus and his followers claimed neither. Instead, despite the apparent conflict with the goal of ], they claimed to continue searching for something that might be knowable. | |||
A skeptical scenario is a hypothetical situation which can be used in an argument for ] about a particular claim or class of claims. Usually the scenario posits the existence of a deceptive power that deceives our senses and undermines the justification of knowledge otherwise accepted as justified, and is proposed in order to call into question our ordinary claims to knowledge on the grounds that we cannot exclude the possibility of skeptical scenarios being true. Skeptical scenarios have received a great deal of attention in modern Western philosophy. | |||
The first major skeptical scenario in modern ] appears in ]' '']''. At the end of the first Meditation Descartes writes: "I will suppose... that some evil demon of the utmost power and cunning has employed all his energies to deceive me." | |||
Empiricus, as the most systematic and dogmatic author of the works by Helenistic sceptics which have survived, noted that there are at least ''ten modes'' of skepticism. These modes may be broken down into three categories: we may be skeptical of ''the subjective perceiver, of the objective world'', and ''the relation between perceiver and the world''.<ref>On the ten modes, see Sextus Empiricus. ''Outlines of Skepticism'' I.35-164.</ref> | |||
* The "]", also known as "Descartes' evil demon", was first proposed by René Descartes. It invokes the possibility of a being who could deliberately mislead one into falsely believing everything that you take to be true. | |||
* The "]" hypothesis is cast in contemporary scientific terms. It supposes that one might be a disembodied brain kept alive in a vat and fed false sensory signals by a ]. Further, it asserts that since a brain in a vat would have no way of knowing that it was a brain in a vat, you cannot prove that you are not a brain in a vat. | |||
* The "]", proposed by both René Descartes and ], supposes reality to be indistinguishable from a dream. | |||
* The "]", most notably proposed by ], suggests that we cannot prove that the world was not created five minutes ago (along with false memories and false evidence suggesting that it was not only five minutes old). | |||
* The "]" or "] hypothesis" suggests that everyone, or even the entire universe, might be inside a ] or ]. | |||
* The "]" theory that claims that knowledge of the world is an illusion of the Self. | |||
===Epistemological skepticism=== | |||
''Subjectively'', both the powers of the senses and of reasoning may vary across persons. And since knowledge is a product of one and/or the other, and since neither are reliable, knowledge would seem to be in trouble. For instance, a ] person sees the world quite differently from everyone else. Moreover, we cannot even give preference on the basis of the power of reason, i.e., by treating the rational animal as a carrier of greater knowledge than the irrational animal. For the irrational animal is still adept at navigating their environment, which presupposes the ability to know about some aspects of the environment. | |||
Skepticism, as an ] view, calls into question whether knowledge is possible at all. This is distinct from other known skeptical practices, including ], as it targets knowledge in general instead of individual types of knowledge. | |||
Skeptics argue that belief in something does not justify an assertion of knowledge of it. In this, skeptics oppose ], which states that there are basic positions that are self-justified or beyond justification, without reference to others. (One example of such foundationalism may be found in ]'s ''Ethics''.) | |||
Secondly, the personality of the individual might also have an impact on what they observe, since (it is argued) preferences are based on sense-impressions, differences in preferences can be attributed to differences in the way that people are affected by the object. (Empiricus:56) | |||
Among other arguments, skeptics use the ] and the ] to claim that no ] belief can be achieved. This position is known as "global skepticism" or "]." ] have used the same ] as a justification for demanding the validity of basic beliefs.{{Citation needed|date=January 2020}} Epistemological ] rejects the possibility of human knowledge, but not necessarily knowledge in general. | |||
Third, the perceptions of each individual sense seemingly have nothing in common with the other senses: i.e., the color "red" has little to do with the feeling of touching a red object. This is manifest when our senses "disagree" with each other: for example, a mirage presents certain visible features, but is not responsive to any other kind of sense. In that case, our other senses defeat the impressions of sight. But we may also be lacking enough powers of sense to understand the world in its entirety: if we had an extra sense, then we might know of things in a way that the present five senses are unable to advise us of. Given that our senses can be shown to be unreliable by appealing to other senses, and so our senses may be incomplete (relative to some more perfect sense that we lack), then it follows that all of our senses may be unreliable. (Empiricus:58) | |||
There are two different categories of epistemological skepticism, which can be referred to as mitigated and unmitigated skepticism. The two forms are contrasting but are still true forms of ]. Mitigated skepticism does not accept "strong" or "strict" knowledge claims but does, however, approve specific weaker ones. These weaker claims can be assigned the title of "virtual knowledge", but must be to justified belief. Some mitigated skeptics are also ], arguing that knowledge does not require certainty. Mitigated skeptics hold that knowledge does not require certainty and that many beliefs are, in practice, certain to the point that they can be safely acted upon in order to live significant and meaningful lives. Unmitigated skepticism rejects both claims of virtual knowledge and strong knowledge.<ref name="SKEPTICISM">{{cite journal|title=SKEPTICISM|journal=Encyclopedia of Empiricism|year=1997}}</ref> Characterising knowledge as strong, weak, virtual or genuine can be determined differently depending on a person's viewpoint as well as their characterisation of knowledge. Unmitigated skeptics believe that objective truths are unknowable and that man should live in an isolated environment in order to win mental peace. This is because everything, according to them, is changing and relative. The refusal to make judgments is of uttermost importance since there is no knowledge; only probable opinions.<ref name="SKEPTICISM"/> | |||
Fourth, our circumstances when we do any perceiving may be either natural or unnatural, i.e., we may be either in a state of wakefulness or that of sleep. But it is entirely possible that things in the world really are exactly as they appear to be to those in unnatural states (i.e., if everything were an elaborate dream). (Empiricus:59) | |||
===Criticism=== | |||
We have reasons for doubt that are based on the ''relationship between objective "facts" and subjective experience''. The positions, distances, and places of objects would seem to affect how they are perceived by the person: for instance, the portico may appear tapered when viewed from one end, but symmetrical when viewed at the other; and these features are different. Because they are different features, to believe the object has both properties at the same time is to believe it has two contradictory properties. Since this is absurd, we must suspend judgment about what properties it possesses. (Empiricus:63) | |||
Philosophical skepticism has been criticized in various ways. Some criticisms see it as a ] while others point out that it is implausible, psychologically impossible, or a pointless intellectual game. This position is based on the idea that philosophical skepticism not only rejects the existence of knowledge but seems to make knowledge claims itself at the same time.<ref name="Popkin">{{cite web |last1=Popkin |first1=Richard H. |title=skepticism |url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/skepticism |website=www.britannica.com |access-date=23 August 2022 |language=en}}</ref><ref name="Bailey1990">{{cite journal |last1=Bailey |first1=Alan |title=Pyrrhonean Scepticism and the Self-Refutation Argument |journal=The Philosophical Quarterly |date=1990 |volume=40 |issue=158 |pages=27–44 |doi=10.2307/2219965 |jstor=2219965 |issn=0031-8094}}</ref><ref>Kreeft p. 373</ref> For example, to claim that there is no knowledge seems to be itself a knowledge claim. This problem is particularly relevant for versions of philosophical skepticism that deny any form of knowledge. So the global skeptic denies that any claim is ] justified but then goes on to provide arguments in an attempt to rationally justify their denial.<ref name="Bailey1990"/> Some philosophical skeptics have responded to this objection by restricting the denial of knowledge to certain fields without denying the existence of knowledge in general. Another defense consists in understanding philosophical skepticism not as a theory but as a tool or a ]. In this case, it may be used fruitfully to reject and improve philosophical systems despite its shortcomings as a theory.<ref name="Popkin"/><ref name="LeMorvan2011"/> | |||
Another criticism holds that philosophical skepticism is highly counterintuitive by pointing out how far removed it is from regular life.<ref name="DeRose1999"/><ref name="Popkin"/> For example, it seems very impractical, if not psychologically impossible, to suspend all beliefs at the same time. And even if it were possible, it would not be advisable since "the complete skeptic would wind up starving to death or walking into walls or out of windows".<ref name="Popkin"/> This criticism can allow that there are some arguments that support philosophical skepticism. However, it has been claimed that they are not nearly strong enough to support such a radical conclusion.<ref name="DeRose1999"/> ] philosophers follow this line of thought by arguing that regular common-sense beliefs are much more reliable than the skeptics' intricate arguments.<ref name="DeRose1999"/> ], for example, tried to refute skepticism about the existence of the external world, not by engaging with its complex arguments, but by using a simple observation: ]. For Moore, this observation is a reliable source of knowledge incompatible with external world skepticism since it entails that at least two physical objects exist.<ref name="Baldwin2004">{{cite web |last1=Baldwin |first1=Tom |title=George Edward Moore: 6. Common Sense and Certainty |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore/#6 |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=1 September 2022 |date=2010}}</ref><ref name="DeRose1999">{{cite book |last1=DeRose |first1=Keith |last2=Warfield |first2=Ted A. |title=Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader |date=1999 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-511827-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tjENAQAAMAAJ |language=en |chapter=1. Introduction: Responding to Skepticism}}</ref> | |||
We may also observe that the things we perceive are, in a sense, polluted by experience. Any given perception -- say, of a chair -- will always be perceived within some context or other (i.e., next to a table, on a mat, etc.) Since this is the case, we can only speak of ideas as they occur in the context of the other things that are paired with it. We can never know of the true nature of the thing, but only how it appears to us in context. (Empiricus: 64) | |||
A closely related objection sees philosophical skepticism as an "idle academic exercise" or a "waste of time".<ref name="Stroud1984a">{{cite book |last1=Stroud |first1=Barry |last2=Stroud |first2=Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry |title=The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism |date=5 July 1984 |publisher=OUP Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-824761-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yrHmCwAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Preface}}</ref> This is often based on the idea that, because of its initial implausibility and distance from everyday life, it has little or no practical value.<ref name="Popkin"/><ref name="LeMorvan2011"/> In this regard, ] compares the position of radical skepticism to a border fortress that is best ignored: it is impregnable but its garrison does not pose any threat since it never sets foot outside the fortress.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Schulte |first1=Günter |title=Gehirnfunktion Und Willensfreiheit. Schopenhauers Neurophilosophische Wende |journal=Schopenhauer Jahrbuch |date=2007 |volume=88 |pages=51–70 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHGUW-3}}</ref> One defense of philosophical skepticism is that it has had important impacts on the ] at large and not just among skeptical philosophers. This is due to its critical attitude, which remains a constant challenge to the epistemic foundations of various philosophical theories. It has often provoked creative responses from other philosophers when trying to modify the affected theory to avoid the problem of skepticism.<ref name="Popkin"/><ref name="Greco2009">{{cite book |last1=Greco |first1=John |title=The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism |date=2 September 2009 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-518321-4 |pages=3–7 |edition=1 |url=https://academic.oup.com/edited-volume/28229/chapter-abstract/213259164 |language=en |chapter=Introduction}}</ref> | |||
Along the same lines, the skeptic may insist that all things are relative, by arguing that: | |||
# Absolute appearances either differ from relative appearances, or they do not. | |||
# If absolutes do not differ from relatives, then they are themselves relative. | |||
# But if absolutes do differ from relatives, then they are relative, because all things that differ must differ from something; and to "differ" from something is to be relative to something. (Empiricus:67) | |||
According to Pierre Le Morvan, there are two very common negative responses to philosophical skepticism. The first understands it as a threat to all kinds of philosophical theories and strives to disprove it. According to the second, philosophical skepticism is a useless distraction and should better be avoided altogether. Le Morvan himself proposes a positive third alternative: to use it as a philosophical tool in a few selected cases to overcome prejudices and foster practical wisdom.<ref name="LeMorvan2011">{{cite journal |last1=Le Morvan |first1=Pierre |title=Healthy Skepticism and Practical Wisdom |journal=Logos & Episteme |date=2011 |volume=2 |issue=1 |pages=87–102 |doi=10.5840/logos-episteme20112151|doi-access=free }}</ref> | |||
Finally, we have reason to disbelieve that we know anything by looking at problems in understanding ''the objects themselves''. Things, when taken individually, may appear to be very different than when they are in mass quantities: for instance, the shavings of a goat's horn are white when taken alone, yet the horn intact is black. | |||
== History of Western skepticism == | |||
=== Ancient Eastern Skepticism === | |||
] | |||
====Buddhism==== | |||
Buddhist skepticism differs substantially from western philosophical skepticism in several ways: The world of sensory appearances as in Hinduism is often called "maya" and is considered an illusion, which is different from doubting that it exists or can represent something beyond itself. There are also levels of understanding such that what is real or true on one level may be unreal or false on what is thought to be a higher level, while among the Hellenists logic was rarely compromised or rejected as fully, even by Pyrrho or Zeno the Cynic, though on a behavioral or ethical level for Hindus and Buddhists there is a kind of logic about collecting karma and its relation to how or where we will be re-born on the famous Wheel of Karma. A major difference is that suffering is ultimately illusion in much Indian Buddhism while it is real and hard to eliminate in most Hindu understanding. | |||
=== Ancient Greek skepticism === | |||
* ] is said to have touched the earth at the time of his enlightenment so that it could witness his enlightenment. In this way, Buddhism does not claim that knowledge is unattainable. | |||
], marble head, Roman copy, Archeological Museum of Corfu]]{{Pyrrhonism sidebar}} | |||
* Buddhism places less emphasis on truth and knowledge than western philosophical skepticism. Instead, it emphasizes the goal of '']'', which, although often translated as ''enlightenment'', does not imply truth or knowledge. | |||
Ancient Greek skeptics were not "skeptics" in the contemporary sense of selective, localized doubt. Their concerns were epistemological, noting that truth claims could not be adequately supported, and psychotherapeutic, noting that beliefs caused mental perturbation. | |||
* At least in its manifestation of ] texts that form the core of ], the anti-essentialist aspect of Buddhism makes it an anti-philosophy. From that stance, truth exists solely within the contexts that assert them. | |||
The ] tradition of systematic ] goes back at least as far as ] of ] (b. {{circa|360 BCE}}) and arguably to ] (b. {{circa|570 BCE}}). Parts of skepticism also appear among the "5th century ] develop forms of debate which are ancestors of skeptical argumentation. They take pride in arguing in a persuasive fashion for both sides of an issue."<ref>{{cite book|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/skepticism-ancient/|title=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|first=Katja|last=Vogt|editor-first=Edward N.|editor-last=Zalta|year=2019|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|via=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> | |||
In China, ] introduced a form of naturalism based on a rational critique of the superstition that was overtaking ] and ] in the first century CE. His neo-] philosophy was based on a secular, rational practice not unlike the scientific method. | |||
In ], ] and ] were the two schools of skeptical philosophy. Subsequently, the words ''Academic'' and ''Pyrrhonist'' were often used to mean ''skeptic''. | |||
====Jain Philosophy of Anekantavada and Syadavada==== | |||
{{Main|Anekantavada|Syadvada}} | |||
'''Anekāntavāda ''' also known as the principle of relative ], is one of the basic principles of ]. According to this, the truth or the reality is perceived differently from different points of view, and that no single point of view is the complete truth.<ref>{{cite book | last =Dundas | first =Paul | coauthors =John Hinnels ed. | title =The Jains | publisher =Routledge | year =2002 | location =London | isbn =0-415-26606-8 }} </ref> <ref>{{cite journal | last =Koller | first =John M. | title =Syadvada as the Epistemological Key to the Jaina Middle Way Metaphysics of Anekantavada | journal =Philosophy East and West | volume =Vol. 50 | issue =Iss. 3 | pages =400–7 | location =Honululu | url =http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8221(200007)50%3A3%3C400%3ASATEKT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-5 | issn =00318221 | accessdate =2007-10-01 | month =July | year =2000 | doi =10.1353/pew.2000.0009 }}</ref> Jain doctrine states that, an object has infinite modes of existence and qualities and, as such, they cannot be completely perceived in all its aspects and manifestations, due to inherent limitations of the humans. Anekāntavāda is literally the doctrine of non-onesidedness or manifoldness; it is often translated as "non-absolutism". ] is the theory of conditioned predication which provides an expression to anekānta by recommending that epithet “Syād” be attached to every expression. <ref>{{cite book | last =Chatterjea | first =Tara | title =Knowledge and Freedom in Indian Philosophy | publisher =Lexington Books | year =2001 | location =Lanham, MD | isbn =739106929 }} p. 77-87 </ref> Syādvāda is not only an extension of Anekānta ], but a separate system of logic capable of standing on its own force. As reality is complex, no single proposition can express the nature of reality fully. Thus the term “syāt” should be prefixed before each proposition giving it a conditional point of view and thus removing any dogmatism in the statement. .<ref> {{cite journal | last =Koller | first =John M. | title =Syādvāda as the ] key to the Jaina middle way metaphysics of Anekāntavāda | journal =Philosophy East and West. | volume = vol. 50 | issue = 3 |pages=400–8 | location =Honululu | month =July | year =2000 | url =http://proquest.umi.com/pqdweb?did=59942245&Fmt=4&clientId=71080&RQT=309&VName=PQD | issn =00318221 | accessdate =2007-10-01 }} | |||
</ref> | |||
The seven propositions also known as ] are<ref>{{cite book | last =Grimes | first =John | title =A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English | publisher =SUNY Press | year =1996 | location =New York | isbn =0791430677 }} p. 312</ref>: | |||
==== Pyrrhonism ==== | |||
#'''''Syād-asti''''' – “in some ways it is”, | |||
{{Main|Pyrrhonism}} | |||
#'''''syād-nāsti''''' - “in some ways it is not”, | |||
Like other ], the goal of Pyrrhonism was ], which the Pyrrhonists sought through achieving ] (an untroubled state of mind), which they found could be induced by producing a state of ] (suspension of judgment) regarding non-evident matters. Epoché could be produced by pitting one ] against another to undermine belief, and by questioning whether a belief could be justified. In support of this questioning Pyrrhonists developed the ] cited above (the ] and the ])<ref name="Thorsrud 2009 108–109">{{Cite book|last=Thorsrud|first=Harald|title=Ancient scepticism|date=2009|publisher=Acumen|isbn=978-1-84465-409-3|location=Stocksfield |pages=108–109|oclc=715184861|quote=Undecidability and the ten modes As part of his Pyrrhonian revival Aenesidemus assembled various kinds of skeptical arguments, or modes, designed to induce ''epoche''.}}</ref> demonstrating that beliefs cannot be justified:<ref>Diogenes Laërtius 9:80–88</ref> | |||
#'''''syād-asti-nāsti''''' - “in some ways it is and it is not”, | |||
#{{IAST|'''''syād-asti-avaktavyaḥ''''' - “in some ways it is and it is indescribable”, | |||
#'''''syād-nāsti-avaktavyaḥ''''' - “in some ways it is not and it is indescribable”, | |||
#'''''syād-asti-nāsti-avaktavyaḥ''''' - “in some ways it is, it is not and it is indescribable”, | |||
#'''''syād-avaktavyaḥ'''''- “in some ways it is indescribable”}} | |||
===== Pyrrho of Elis ===== | |||
Each of these seven propositions examines the complex and multifaceted reality from a relative point of view of time, space, substance and mode. To ignore the complexity of the objects is to commit the fallacy of dogmatism. | |||
{{Main|Pyrrho}} | |||
According to an account of Pyrrho's life by his student ], Pyrrho extolled a way to become happy and tranquil: | |||
<blockquote>'The things themselves are equally indifferent, and unstable, and indeterminate, and therefore neither our senses nor our opinions are either true or false. For this reason then we must not trust them, but be without opinions, and without bias, and without wavering, saying of every single thing that it no more is than is not, or both is and is not, or neither is nor is not.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Eusebius |title=Praeparatio Evangelica Book XIV |url=https://www.tertullian.org/fathers/eusebius_pe_14_book14.htm |website=Tertullian Project |access-date=27 January 2023}}</ref></blockquote> | |||
== Schools of philosophical skepticism == | |||
===== Aenesidemus ===== | |||
Philosophical skepticism begins with the claim that the skeptic currently does not have knowledge. Some adherents maintain that knowledge is, in theory, possible. It could be argued that ] held that view. He appears to have thought that if people continue to ask questions they might eventually come to have knowledge; but that they did not have it yet. Some skeptics have gone further and claimed that true knowledge is impossible, for example the Academic school in Ancient Greece well after the time of Carneades. A third skeptical approach would be neither to accept nor reject the possibility of knowledge. | |||
{{Main|Aenesidemus}} | |||
Pyrrhonism faded as a movement following the death of Pyrrho's student Timon.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Thorsrud|first=Harald|title=Ancient scepticism|date=2009|publisher=Acumen|isbn=978-1-84465-409-3|location=Stocksfield |pages=120–121|oclc=715184861|quote=Pyrrhonism, in whatever form it might have taken after Timon's death in 230 BCE, was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention}}</ref> The Academy became slowly more dogmatic<ref name=":5">{{Cite book|last=Thorsrud|first=Harald|title=Ancient scepticism|date=2009|publisher=Acumen|isbn=978-1-84465-409-3|location=Stocksfield |pages=102–103|oclc=715184861|quote=Aenesidemus criticized his fellow Academics for being dogmatic...Aenesidemus committed his scepticism to writing probably some time in the early-to-mid first century BCE...leading Aenesidemus to dismiss them as "Stoics fighting against Stoics."}}</ref> such that in the first century BCE Aenesidemus denounced the Academics as "Stoics fighting against Stoics", breaking with the Academy to revive Pyrrhonism.<ref name=":5"/> Aenesidemus's best known contribution to skepticism was his now-lost book, ''Pyrrhonian Discourses'', which is only known to us through ], ], and to a lesser extent ]. The skeptical arguments most closely associated with Aenesidemus are the ten modes described above designed to induce ''].'' <ref name="Thorsrud 2009 108–109"/> | |||
===== Sextus Empiricus ===== | |||
Skepticism can be either about everything or about particular areas. A 'global' skeptic argues that he does not absolutely know anything to be either true or false. Academic global skepticism has great difficulty in supporting this claim while maintaining philosophical rigor, since it seems to require that nothing can be known — except for the knowledge that nothing can be known, though in its probabilistic form it can use and support the notion of weight of evidence. Thus, some probibilists avoid extreme skepticism by maintaining that they merely are 'reasonably certain' (or largely believe') some things are real or true. As for using probabilistic arguments to defend skepticism, in a sense this enlarges or increases scepticism, while the defence of empiricism by Empiricus weakens skepticism and strengthens dogmatism by alleging that sensory appearances are beyond doubt. Much later, Kant would re-define "dogmatism" to make indirect realism about the external world seem objectionable. While many Hellenists, outside of Empiricus, would maintain that everyone who is not sceptical about everything is a dogmatist, this position would seem too extreme for most later philosophers. | |||
] | |||
{{Main|Sextus Empiricus}} | |||
The works of ] (c. 200 CE) are the main surviving account of ancient Pyrrhonism. Long before Sextus' time, the Academy had abandoned skepticism and had been destroyed as a formal institution.<ref name=":5" /><ref>{{Cite book|last=Sextus|first=Empiricus|title=Outlines of pyrrhonism|date=1990|publisher=Prometheus Books|others=Robert Gregg Bury|isbn=0-87975-597-0|location=Buffalo, N.Y.|oclc=23367477|quote=Those who believe they have discovered it are the "dogmatists", specially so called - Aristotle, for example, and Epicurus and the Stoics and certain others; Cleitomachus and Carneades and other Academics treat it as inapprehensible:the skeptics keep on searching. Hence it seems reasonable to hold the main types of philosophy are three - the dogmatic, the Academic, and the skeptic.}}</ref><ref>Plutarch, ; cf. Appian, ''Roman History'' {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150912164943/http://www.livius.org/ap-ark/appian/appian_mithridatic_06.html |date=September 12, 2015 }}</ref> Sextus compiled and further developed the Pyrrhonists' skeptical arguments, most of which were directed against the ] but included arguments against all of the schools of ], including the Academic skeptics. | |||
Sextus, as the most systematic author of the works by Hellenistic skeptics which have survived, noted that there are at least ''ten modes'' of skepticism. These modes may be broken down into three categories: one may be skeptical of ''the subjective perceiver, of the objective world'', and ''the relation between perceiver and the world''.<ref>On the ten modes, see Sextus Empiricus. ''Outlines of Skepticism'' I.35–164.</ref> His arguments are as follows. | |||
Nevertheless, A Pyrrhonian global skeptic labors under no such modern constraint, since he only alleged that he, personally, did not know anything and made no statement about the possibility of knowledge. Nor did Arcesilaus feel bound, since he merely corrected Plato's "I only know that I know nothing" by adding "I don't even know that", thus more fully rejecting dogmatism. | |||
''Subjectively'', the powers of the senses and reasoning may vary among different people. And since knowledge is a product of one or the other, and since neither are reliable, knowledge would seem to be in trouble. For instance, a ] person sees the world quite differently from everyone else. Moreover, one cannot even give preference based on the power of reason, i.e., by treating the rational animal as a carrier of greater knowledge than the irrational animal, since the irrational animal is still adept at navigating their environment, which suggests the ability to "know" about some aspects of the environment. | |||
] deny that people do or can have knowledge of a particular area. They may be skeptical about the possibility of one form of knowledge without doubting other forms. Different kinds of local skepticism may emerge, depending on the area. A person may doubt the truth value of different types of journalism, for example, depending on the types of media they trust. | |||
Secondly, the personality of the individual might also influence what they observe, since (it is argued) preferences are based on sense-impressions, differences in preferences can be attributed to differences in the way that people are affected by the object. (Empiricus:56) | |||
In ], skepticism was established by ] (1058-1111), known in the West as "Algazel", as part of the orthodox ] school of ]. It has been argued that ]' ideas from '']'' may have been influenced by the work of Al-Ghazali, whose method of skepticism shares many similarities with Descartes' method.<ref name=Najm>{{citation|title=The Place and Function of Doubt in the Philosophies of Descartes and Al-Ghazali|first=Sami M.|last=Najm|journal=Philosophy East and West|volume=16|issue=3-4|date=July-October 1966|pages=133–41}}</ref> | |||
Third, the perceptions of each individual sense seemingly have nothing in common with the other senses: i.e., the color "red" has little to do with the feeling of touching a red object. This is manifest when our senses "disagree" with each other: for example, a mirage presents certain visible features, but is not responsive to any other kind of sense. In that case, our other senses defeat the impressions of sight. But one may also be lacking enough powers of sense to understand the world in its entirety: if one had an extra sense, then one might know of things in a way that the present five senses are unable to advise us of. Given that our senses can be shown to be unreliable by appealing to other senses, and so our senses may be incomplete (relative to some more perfect sense that one lacks), then it follows that all of our senses may be unreliable. (Empiricus:58) | |||
==Epistemology and skepticism== | |||
Skepticism, as an ] argument, poses the question of whether knowledge, in the first place, is possible. Skeptics argue that the belief in something does not necessarily justify an assertion of knowledge of it. In this, skeptics oppose ], such as Spinoza maintained which states that there have to be some basic positions that are self-justified or beyond justification, without reference to others. The skeptical response to this can take several approaches. First, claiming that "basic positions" must exist amounts to the logical fallacy of ] combined with the ] {{Fact|date=March 2007}}. | |||
Fourth, our circumstances when one perceives anything may be either natural or unnatural, i.e., one may be either in a state of wakefulness or sleep. But it is entirely possible that things in the world really are exactly as they appear to be to those in unnatural states (i.e., if everything were an elaborate dream). (Empiricus:59) | |||
Among other arguments, skeptics used ], named after ], to claim no certain belief could be achieved. ]s have used the same trilemma as a justification for demanding the validity of basic beliefs. | |||
One can have reasons for doubt that are based on the ''relationship between objective "facts" and subjective experience''. The positions, distances, and places of objects would seem to affect how they are perceived by the person: for instance, the portico may appear tapered when viewed from one end, but symmetrical when viewed at the other; and these features are different. Because they are different features, to believe the object has both properties at the same time is to believe it has two contradictory properties. Since this is absurd, one must suspend judgment about what properties it possesses due to the contradictory experiences. (Empiricus:63) | |||
This skeptical approach is rarely taken to its pyrrhonean extreme by most practitioners. Several modifications have arisen over the years, including the following: | |||
One may also observe that the things one perceives are, in a sense, polluted by experience. Any given perception—say, of a chair—will always be perceived within some context or other (i.e., next to a table, on a mat, etc.) Since this is the case, one often only speaks of ideas as they occur in the context of the other things that are paired with it, and therefore, one can never know of the true nature of the thing, but only how it appears to us in context. (Empiricus: 64) | |||
] would not claim to have knowledge but will adhere to conclusions on some criterion such as utility, aesthetics, or other personal criteria without claiming that any conclusion is actually "true". | |||
Along the same lines, the skeptic may insist that all things are relative, by arguing that: | |||
Philosophical fideism (as opposed to religious ]) would assert the truth of some proposition, but does so without asserting certainty. | |||
# Absolute appearances either differ from relative appearances, or they do not. | |||
# If absolutes do not differ from relatives, then they are themselves relative. | |||
# But if absolutes do differ from relatives, then they are relative, because all things that differ must differ from something; and to "differ" from something is to be relative to something. (Empiricus:67) | |||
Finally, one has reason to disbelieve that one knows anything by looking at problems in understanding objects by themselves. Things, when taken individually, may appear to be very different from when they are in mass quantities: for instance, the shavings of a goat's horn are white when taken alone, yet the horn intact is black. {{citation needed|date=June 2022}} | |||
Some forms of ] would accept utility as a provisional guide to truth but not necessarily a universal decision-maker. | |||
=====Skeptical arguments===== | |||
== Motivations for external world skepticism == | |||
The ancient Greek ] developed sets of arguments to demonstrate that claims about reality cannot be adequately justified. Two sets of these arguments are well known. The oldest set is known as ]—although whether he invented the ] or just systematized them from prior Pyrrhonist works is unknown. The tropes represent reasons for ] (]). These are as follows: | |||
{{Original research|date=October 2008}} | |||
] offers one argument as to why anyone would want to question the reliability of perception. Hume argued that people can only know about the external world through perceptions of it, and the accuracy of these perceptions cannot be proven. {{Fact|date=February 2007}} | |||
# Different animals manifest different modes of perception; | |||
In addition to Hume's argument for external world skepticism, there is another more famous argument. This is ]' famous ]: Descartes was writing one evening in his room, and he thought to himself (paraphrasing very loosely): What if I am asleep in bed right now, and only '']ing'' that I am awake, and writing? Isn't that at least possible? Then he said, well surely, I can tell when I am awake and when I am asleep. I can tell the difference between wakefulness and a dream. All sorts of strange things happen in dreams; I pass unaccountably from scene to scene when I'm dreaming; I don't have any long memory of what happened in a day, when I'm dreaming; and so forth. Then Descartes said: Haven't I had those very thoughts in some of my dreams? Sometimes, when I was dreaming, I was convinced that I was awake! I even tried to test that I was awake, when I was dreaming, and the tests convinced me that I was awake! But I was wrong; I ''was'' dreaming. Isn't it quite possible that the same thing is happening to me ''right now''? Isn't it possible that I am dreaming that I can test whether I'm awake or asleep -- and of course, in my dream, I pass the test? So it seems really vivid to me right now that I'm awake -- but in fact, I'm ''asleep''? | |||
# Similar differences are seen among individual men; | |||
# For the same man, information perceived with the senses is self-contradictory | |||
# Furthermore, it varies from time to time with physical changes | |||
# In addition, this data differs according to local relations | |||
# Objects are known only indirectly through the medium of air, moisture, etc. | |||
# These objects are in a condition of perpetual change in color, temperature, size and motion | |||
# All perceptions are relative and interact one upon another | |||
# Our impressions become less critical through repetition and custom | |||
# All men are brought up with different beliefs, under different laws and social conditions | |||
Another set are known as ]: | |||
Well, Descartes said to himself, I guess there ''aren't'' any definite signs, or tests, that I could use to tell whether I'm asleep or dreaming. I could, after all, be dreaming those very tests. I have experience of doing that, thinking that I passed the test for being awake, when really I was only dreaming. So there ''isn't any way'' to tell that I am awake now. I cannot possibly prove that I am awake. So, Descartes said to himself, I don't really know that I am awake now and writing in the evening. For all I really ''know'', I could be asleep. | |||
# '']'' – The uncertainty demonstrated by the differences of opinions among philosophers and people in general. | |||
Now we can go on and examine this argument in more detail. For one thing, why does Descartes think that he doesn't know he's awake and writing? Well, he might be asleep. But what difference does that make? The difference that it makes is that ''his faculty of sense''-''perception would not be reliable'' if he were asleep. In other words, if he were asleep, it would seem to him that he is seeing, feeling, and hearing various things; but he wouldn't really be. In that case, of course, his faculty of perception ''wouldn't'' be reliable. But Descartes appears to go further than that: he appears to be saying that since he ''might'' be dreaming, since he can't rule out the hypothesis that he is dreaming right now, that also means that his faculty of perception is not reliable. | |||
# ''Progress ]'' – All proof rests on matters themselves in need of proof, and so on to infinity, i.e, the ]. | |||
# '']'' – All things are changed as their relations become changed, or, as we look upon them from different points of view. | |||
# '']'' – The truth asserted is based on an unsupported assumption. | |||
# '']'' – The truth asserted involves a circularity of proofs. | |||
According to ] "the five tropes can be regarded as the most radical and most precise formulation of philosophical skepticism that has ever been given. In a sense, they are still irresistible today."<ref>Brochard, V., ''The Greek Skeptics''.</ref> | |||
To many people, Descartes' position may seem absurd. Most people simply feel that of course they can tell that they're not dreaming. Here, though, Descartes could reply that maybe you can, but ''maybe'' you're just ''dreaming'' that you can tell the difference. If you say you ''can'' tell the difference between being awake and being asleep, then you are assuming that you're awake, in which case you're ] against the skeptic. | |||
==== Academic skepticism ==== | |||
Another ] sort of response to Descartes' argument is that one can tell that one's ] is reliable, and here's how: When one sees something, like that cow chewing on daisies, one can go over to the cow, touch it, hear it, lean on it, and so forth. That confirms that one really is seeing the cow. In the same way, when one hears something, like a marching band outside, one can step outside, and look at the marching band, talk to the members of the band, and so forth. That confirms that one heard the band outside. Throughout a person's life they've had so many experiences like this that they are practically certain that, in the more obvious cases anyway, their faculty of perception works -- it's generally reliable. | |||
{{Main|Academic skepticism}} | |||
Pyrrho's thinking subsequently influenced the ], arising first in the ] of the ] under ] (c. 315 – 241 BCE) and then the ] under ] (c. 213–129 BCE). ], a student of Carneades, interpreted his teacher's philosophy as suggesting an account of knowledge based on truth-likeness. The Roman politician and philosopher, ], was also an adherent of the skepticism of the New Academy, even though a return to a more ]tic orientation of the school was already beginning to take place. | |||
==== Augustine on skepticism ==== | |||
Descartes' skeptic will reply to this in much the same way as the previous objection: You might just be ''dreaming'' that you are touching, hearing, and leaning on the cow. That marching band might just be part of a dream. For that matter you might only be ''dreaming'' that your faculty of perception has been generally reliable. If you argue you're not dreaming as your faculty of perception is reliable, then you are once again begging the question. First, you must establish that you're not dreaming, and that's impossible. Thus, you can't know that your faculty of perception is reliable. | |||
] | |||
In 386 CE, ] published ''Contra Academicos'' (Against the Academic Skeptics), which argued against claims made by the Academic Skeptics (266–90 BCE) on the following grounds: | |||
* Objection from Error: Through logic, Augustine argues that philosophical skepticism does not lead to happiness like the Academic Skeptics claim. His arguments is summarized as: | |||
*# A wise man lives according to reason, and thus is able to be happy. | |||
*# One who is searching for knowledge but never finds it is in error. | |||
*# Imperfection objection: People in error are not happy, because being in error is an imperfection, and people cannot be happy with an imperfection. | |||
*# Conclusion: One who is still seeking knowledge cannot be happy.<ref name=":1">{{Cite book|title=Augustine and academic skepticism: a philosophical study|last=Dutton|first=Blake D.|isbn=978-1-5017-0355-3|location=Ithaca |publisher=Cornell University Press |oclc=951625897|year= 2016}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|title=Classical and contemporary readings in the philosophy of religion|last=Hick|first= John|date=1970|publisher=Prentice-Hall|isbn=978-0-13-135269-8|edition=2nd|location=Englewood Cliffs, NJ|oclc=90682|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/classicalcontemp0000hick}}</ref> | |||
* Error of Non-Assent: Augustine's argument that suspending belief does not fully prevent one from error. His argument is summarized below. | |||
*# Introduction of the error: Let P be true. If a person fails to believe P due to ] in order to avoid error, the person is also committing an error. | |||
*# The Anecdote of the Two Travelers: Travelers A and B are trying to reach the same destination. At a fork in the road, a poor shepherd tells them to go left. Traveler A immediately believes him and reaches the correct destination. Traveler B suspends belief, and instead believes in the advice of a well-dressed townsman to go right, because his advice seems more persuasive. However, the townsman is actually a ''samardocus'' (con man) so Traveler B never reaches the correct destination. | |||
*# The Anecdote of the Adulterer: A man suspends belief that adultery is bad, and commits adultery with another man's wife because it is persuasive to him. Under Academic Skepticism, this man cannot be charged because he acted on what was persuasive to him without assenting belief. | |||
*# Conclusion: Suspending belief exposes individuals to an error as defined by the Academic Skeptics.<ref name=":1" /> | |||
*# | |||
=== Skepticism's revival in the sixteenth century === <!--] and ] redirect here---> | |||
Additionally, a sharper skeptic might make another remark about seeing the cow and hearing the marching band. Because, after all, weren't you ''using'' sense-perception in order to try to argue that your faculty of perception is generally reliable? Think about that: in order to show that your sense of sight works, you use your sense of sight and other senses; in order to show that your sense of hearing works, you use your sense of hearing and other senses. And it's not like you can avoid that. It would be really bizarre (though some philosophers have actually tried it){{Fact|date=May 2008}} to try to argue that your senses are reliable, without making use of your senses. But if you make use of your senses, you are begging the question again. You have to assume, or presuppose, that your senses are generally shipshape before you start using them to prove ''anything'', including whether your senses are generally shipshape. | |||
]'s '']'' (published in 1581 as ''Quod nihil scitur'') is one of the crucial texts of '''] skepticism'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA-->.<ref>Francisco Sanchez, , Cambridge University Press, 1989.</ref> | |||
How can you prove that perception is reliable ''without using your senses''? That seems impossible. But how can you use senses without assuming that perception is reliable? If you do that then you're arguing in a circle, you're begging the question. So what's the upshot? That you ''can't'' prove that perception is reliable. If you try, you beg the question, and question-begging is a logical fallacy. | |||
==== Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592) ==== | |||
Notice that this is actually a ''third'' skeptical argument, distinct from Hume's and Descartes', although it is related to both. Hume said you can't prove that your sense-data represent the external world; Descartes said that you can't even prove that you're not dreaming; and this third argument says that you can't prove that perception is reliable without assuming that your senses are reliable and thereby begging the question at issue. | |||
] | |||
The most notable figure of the Skepticism revival in the 1500s, ] wrote about his studies of ] and ] through his ]. | |||
His most notable writings on skepticism occurred in an essay written mostly in 1575–1576, "Apologie de Raimond Sebond", when he was reading ] and trying to translate ]'s writing, including his proof of ]'s natural existence. The reception to Montaigne's translations included some criticisms of Sebond's proof. Montaigne responded to some of them in ''Apologie,'' including a defense for Sebond's logic that is skeptical in nature and similar to Pyrrhonism.<ref>{{Cite book|title=French philosophy, 1572–1675|last=Clarke |first=Desmond M. |isbn=978-0-19-874957-8 |publisher=Oxford University Press |oclc=923850410|year=2016}}</ref><ref name=":2">{{Cite book|title=Skepticism in the modern age: building on the work of Richard Popkin|date=2009|publisher=Brill|editor-last=Maia Neto|editor-first=José Raimundo|editor-last2=Paganini|editor-first2=Gianni|editor-last3=Laursen|editor-first3=John Christian |isbn=978-90-474-3190-9|location=Leiden|oclc=700517388}}</ref> His refutation is as follows: | |||
== Objections == | |||
# Critics claiming Sebond's arguments are weak show how egoistic humans believe that their logic is superior to others'. | |||
===Absolute certainty=== | |||
# Many animals can be observed to be superior to humans in certain respects. To argue this point, Montaigne even writes about dogs who are logical and creates their own ]s to understand the world around them. This was an example used in ]. | |||
First of all, in all three arguments -- Hume's, Descartes', and the circular argument -- the claim is made that ''we'' ''can't'' ''prove'' something or other. We can't prove that sense-data represent an external reality. We can't prove that we're not dreaming. We can't prove that perception, or memory, is reliable. But now ask yourself: just because you can't prove something, does that mean that you don't ''know'' it? Or that you aren't justified in believing it? Take Descartes' dreaming doubt as an example. Suppose you're convinced that you can't prove that you're not dreaming, not without begging the question. And you're even willing to admit that possibility that you are dreaming right now. However, a non-skepticist might reply, who cares? So what if I can't prove, to Descartes' skeptic, that I'm not dreaming? Who cares if there is a possibility that I'm dreaming right now? Does that really matter to my knowledge-claims? | |||
# Since animals also have rationality, the over-glorification of man's mental capabilities is a trap—man's folly. One man's reason cannot be assuredly better than another's as a result. | |||
# Ignorance is even recommended by religion so that an individual can reach faith through obediently following divine instructions to learn, not by one's logic.<ref name=":0">{{Cite book|title=The history of scepticism: from Savonarola to Bayle|last=Popkin|first= Richard Henry|date=2003|publisher=Oxford University Press|others=Popkin, Richard Henry|isbn=978-0-19-535539-0|edition= Rev. and expanded |location=Oxford|oclc=65192690}}</ref> | |||
==== Marin Mersenne (1588–1648) ==== | |||
Descartes himself thought it definitely did matter. Descartes wanted ] -- knowledge beyond any doubt. And so he thought that if you can raise the smallest doubt about something, then you don't really know it. For example, the dreaming doubt raises the possibility that you are not actually reading this article right now; you ''might'' be dreaming; and so Descartes would say (at that point -- later he thought he refuted this skepticism) that you don't ''know'' you're reading this right now. | |||
] | |||
] was an author, mathematician, scientist, and philosopher. He wrote in defense of science and Christianity against atheists and ] before retiring to encourage development of science and the "new philosophy", which includes philosophers like ], ], ], and ]. A major work of his in relation to Skepticism is ''La Verité des Sciences'', in which he argues that although we may not be able to know the true nature of things, we can still formulate certain laws and rules for sense-perceptions through science.<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":2" /><ref>{{Cite book|title=A companion to early modern philosophy|date=2002|publisher=Blackwell Pub|editor-last=Nadler|editor-first=Steven M.|isbn=978-0-631-21800-5|location=Malden, Mass.|oclc=49394201}}</ref> | |||
Additionally, he points out that we do not doubt everything because: | |||
So this forces us to ask ourselves: Do we have to have ''absolute'' ''certainty'', lacking any doubt whatsoever, in order to have knowledge? That would be the absolutely strongest grade of justification possible. And then we would be saying that knowledge is not just ''sufficiently'' ], but ] belief. | |||
* Humans do agree about some things, for example, an ant is smaller than an elephant | |||
* There are natural laws governing our sense-perceptions, such as optics, which allow us to eliminate inaccuracies | |||
* Man created tools such as rulers and scales to measure things and eliminate doubts such as bent oars, pigeons' necks, and round towers. | |||
A Pyrrhonist might refute these points by saying that senses deceive, and thus knowledge turns into infinite regress or circular logic. Thus Mersenne argues that this cannot be the case, since commonly agreed upon rules of thumb can be hypothesized and tested over time to ensure that they continue to hold.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Grotius to Gassendi|date=1992|publisher=Garland Pub|editor-last=Chappell|editor-first=Vere Claiborne|isbn=978-0-8153-0576-7|location=New York|oclc=24846343}}</ref> | |||
Furthermore, if everything can be doubted, the doubt can also be doubted, so on and so forth. Thus, according to Mersenne, something has to be true. Finally, Mersenne writes about all the mathematical, physical, and other scientific knowledge that is true by repeated testing, and has practical use value. Notably, Mersenne was one of the few philosophers who accepted ]' radical ideology—he saw it as a new science of man.<ref name=":0" /> | |||
Many philosophers don't think that such a strong degree of justification is necessary for knowledge. After all, they claim, we can know what the weather is going to be like, just by reading the morning forecast. Sometimes we're wrong; but if we're right then we have knowledge. So they are not particularly worried if they can't prove that they're not dreaming. They think it's extremely unlikely that they're dreaming, and they think they're perfectly well justified in thinking they're awake. And they don't have to ''know'' ''with'' ''absolute'' ''certainty'' that they're awake, of course, to be ''well-justified'' in believing they're awake. | |||
Note too that Descartes himself rejected his skeptical doubts in the end. | |||
=== Skepticism in the seventeenth century === | |||
Here's a second thing you might observe about skepticism: if the skeptic makes absolute certainty a requirement for knowledge, then you could reply that this observation should be applied to skepticism itself. Is skepticism itself entirely beyond doubt? Isn't it possible to raise various kinds of objection to skepticism? So it would appear; but then no one can know that ''skepticism'' is true. So then the skeptic can't know that skepticism is true. But this is actually a bit of a weak reply, because it doesn't really ''refute'' skepticism. The skeptic, after all, may be perfectly happy to admit that no one knows that skepticism is true. The skeptic might rest content saying that skepticism is ''very probably'' true. | |||
] | |||
==== Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) ==== | |||
===Process reliabilism=== | |||
During his long stay in Paris, ] was actively involved in the circle of major skeptics like ] and ] who focus on the study of skepticism and ]. Unlike his fellow skeptic friends, Hobbes never treated skepticism as a main topic for discussion in his works. Nonetheless, Hobbes was still labeled as a religious skeptic by his contemporaries for raising doubts about ] of the ] and his political and psychological explanation of the religions. Although Hobbes himself did not go further to challenge other religious principles, his suspicion for the Mosaic authorship did significant damage to the religious traditions and paved the way for later religious skeptics like ] and ] to further question some of the fundamental beliefs of the Judeo-Christian religious system. Hobbes' answer to skepticism and epistemology was innovatively political: he believed that moral knowledge and religious knowledge were in their nature relative, and there was no absolute standard of truth governing them. As a result, it was out of political reasons that certain truth standards about religions and ethics were devised and established in order to form a functioning government and stable society.<ref name=":0" /><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Missner|first=Marshall|date=1983|title=Skepticism and Hobbes's Political Philosophy|jstor=2709174|journal=Journal of the History of Ideas|volume=44|issue=3|pages=407–427|doi=10.2307/2709174}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Black|first=Sam|date=1997|title=Science and Moral Skepticism in Hobbes|jstor=40231980|journal=Canadian Journal of Philosophy|volume=27|issue=2|pages=173–207|doi=10.1080/00455091.1997.10717477|s2cid=170567466}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|title=Skepticism and political thought in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries|editor=Laursen, John Christian |editor2=Paganini, Gianni|isbn=978-1-4426-4921-7|publisher=University of Toronto Press |oclc=904548214 |year=2015}}</ref>] | |||
A third objection, which especially applies to the circularity argument, comes from the common-sense Scotsman, ]. Reid argued as follows: Suppose the skeptic is right, and perception is not reliable. But perception is just another one of my cognitive processes; and if ''it'' is not reliable then my ''others'' are also bound not to be reliable. All of my faculties came out of the same shop, he said; so if one is faulty the others are bound to be as well. But that means that the faculty of ''reasoning'', which the skeptic uses, is also bound to be unreliable too. In other words, when we reason, we are bound to make errors, and so we can never trust the arguments we give for any claim, a condition that can be extended to be applied to the skeptic's argument for skepticism. So it follows that if the skeptic is right, we should not pay attention to skepticism, since the skeptic arrives at the skeptical conclusion by reasoning. And if the skeptic is wrong, then of course we need not pay attention to skepticism. In either case, we need not take skepticism about the reliability of our faculties seriously. | |||
==== Baruch Spinoza and religious skepticism ==== | |||
== LOGICAL PROOF SKEPTICISM IS CIRCULAR == | |||
] was among the first European philosophers who were religious skeptics. He was quite familiar with the philosophy of ] and unprecedentedly extended the application of the Cartesian method to the religious context by analyzing religious texts with it. Spinoza sought to dispute the knowledge-claims of the ] religious system by examining its two foundations: the ] and the ]. He claimed that all Cartesian knowledge, or the rational knowledge should be accessible to the entire population. Therefore, the Scriptures, aside from those by Jesus, should not be considered the secret knowledge attained from God but just the imagination of the prophets. The Scriptures, as a result of this claim, could not serve as a base for knowledge and were reduced to simple ancient historical texts. Moreover, Spinoza also rejected the possibility for the Miracles by simply asserting that people only considered them miraculous due to their lack of understanding of the nature. By rejecting the validity of the Scriptures and the Miracles, Spinoza demolished the foundation for religious knowledge-claim and established his understanding of the Cartesian knowledge as the sole authority of knowledge-claims. Despite being deeply skeptical of the religions, Spinoza was in fact exceedingly anti-skeptical towards reason and rationality. He steadfastly confirmed the legitimacy of reason by associating it with the acknowledgement of God, and thereby skepticism with the rational approach to knowledge was not due to problems with the rational knowledge but from the fundamental lack of understanding of God. Spinoza's religious skepticism and anti-skepticism with reason thus helped him transform epistemology by separating the theological knowledge-claims and the rational knowledge-claims.<ref name=":0" /><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Batnitzky|first=Leora|date=December 2003|title=Spinoza's Critique of Religious Authority: Spinoza's Critique of Miracles |journal=Cardozo Law Review|volume=25|page=57}}</ref> | |||
If Descartes' reasoning can be condensed to "I think, therefore I am", one must realize that such a statement means nothing. In order for the defined concept of "I" to think, then necessarily this concept must exist in the first place. If this concept of "I" did not exist, then by definition it could not think or do anything for that matter. Thus, Descartes' ultimate conclusion that one thinks necessarily presumes that one exists and any further work is built upon this axiomatic definition which means nothing. | |||
==== Pierre Bayle (1647–1706) ==== | |||
In order to truly prove skepticism is circular, all one has to do is prove oneself to be God on paper. To that end: | |||
] | |||
] was a French philosopher in the late 17th century that was described by Richard Popkin to be a "supersceptic" who carried out the sceptic tradition to the extreme. Bayle was born in a Calvinist family in ], and during the early stage of his life, he converted into Catholicism before returning to Calvinism. This conversion between religions caused him to leave France for the more religiously tolerant Holland where he stayed and worked for the rest of his life.<ref name=":0" /> | |||
Bayle believed that truth cannot be obtained through reason and that all human endeavor to acquire absolute knowledge would inevitably lead to failure. Bayle's main approach was highly skeptical and destructive: he sought to examine and analyze all existing theories in all fields of human knowledge in order to show the faults in their reasoning and thus the absurdity of the theories themselves. In his ''magnum opus, ]'' ''(Historical and Critical Dictionary),'' Bayle painstakingly identified the logical flaws in several works throughout the history in order to emphasize the absolute futility of rationality. Bayle's complete nullification of reason led him to conclude that faith is the final and only way to truth.<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":3">{{Cite book|title=The specter of skepticism in the age of Enlightenment|last=Matytsin|first= Anton M.|isbn=978-1-4214-2052-3|location=Baltimore |publisher=Johns Hopkins University Press |oclc=960048885|year=2016}}</ref><ref name=":4">{{Cite journal|last=Lennon|first=Thomas M.|date=2002|title=What Kind of a Skeptic Was Bayle?|journal=Midwest Studies in Philosophy|volume=26-1|pages=258–279|doi=10.1111/1475-4975.261066}}</ref> | |||
Axiom: We take, as an assumption, that set theory exists. | |||
Bayle's real intention behind his extremely destructive works remained controversial. Some described him to be a ], while others speculated him to be a secret ]. However, no matter what his original intention was, Bayle did cast significant influence on the upcoming ] with his destruction of some of the most essential theological ideas and his justification of religious tolerance Atheism in his works.<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":3" /><ref name=":4" /> | |||
Axiom: Choice, by definition, randomly exists relative to a set's expression. | |||
===Skepticism in the Age of Enlightenment=== | |||
Axiom: Relativity is relativity to itself. | |||
==== David Hume (1711–1776) ==== | |||
] was among the most influential proponents of philosophical skepticism during the Age of Enlightenment and one of the most notable voices of the ] and ].<ref name="SEP Hume">Morris, William Edward, and Charlotte R. Brown. 2019 . " {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/19980503005157/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hume/ |date=May 3, 1998 }}." '']''. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab. Retrieved 10 August 2020.</ref><ref name="Britannica Hume">], and ]. 2020 " {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150621091031/https://www.britannica.com/biography/David-Hume#toc12268 |date=June 21, 2015 }}." '']''. Retrieved 10 August 2020.</ref> He especially espoused skepticism regarding ], and questioned what the foundation of ] was, creating the ]. His approach to skepticism is considered even more radical than ] of ].{{According to whom|date=September 2022}} | |||
Hume argued that any coherent idea must be either a mental copy of an ] (a direct sensory ]) or copies of multiple impressions innovatively combined. Since certain human activities like religion, superstition, and ] are not premised on any actual sense-impressions, their claims to knowledge are logically unjustified. Furthermore, Hume even demonstrates that science is merely a psychological phenomenon based on the ]: often, specifically, an assumption of ] relationships that is itself not grounded in any sense-impressions. Thus, even scientific knowledge is logically unjustified, being not actually objective or provable but, rather, mere conjecture flimsily based on our minds perceiving ] between distinct events. Hume thus falls into extreme skepticism regarding the possibility of any certain knowledge. Ultimately, he offers that, at best, a ] is the "only solid foundation for the other sciences".<ref>Hume, David. 1739. . London: John Noon. Retrieved 19 May 2020. p. 7.</ref> | |||
A fractal is a set which defines itself as containing itself and nothing more. | |||
====Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)<!--] and ] redirect here--->==== | |||
A fractal is relatively infinite, with respect to any one Laplacian on the fractal. | |||
{{cleanup rewrite|date=August 2020}} | |||
] | |||
] (1724–1804) tried to provide a ground for empirical science against ]'s skeptical treatment of the notion of cause and effect. Hume (1711–1776) argued that for the notion of cause and effect no analysis is possible which is also acceptable to the empiricist program primarily outlined by ] (1632–1704).<ref>David Hume, '']'' (1739), Book I, "Of the Understanding" and David Hume, '']'' (1748).</ref> But, Kant's attempt to give a ground to knowledge in the empirical sciences at the same time cut off the possibility of knowledge of any other knowledge, especially what Kant called "metaphysical knowledge". So, for Kant, empirical science was legitimate, but metaphysics and philosophy was mostly illegitimate. The most important exception to this demarcation of the legitimate from the illegitimate was ethics, the principles of which Kant argued can be known by pure reason without appeal to the principles required for empirical knowledge. Thus, with respect to metaphysics and philosophy in general (ethics being the exception), Kant was a skeptic. This skepticism as well as the explicit skepticism of ]<ref>See ], '']'' (1792), excerpted in ''Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism'', Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 2000. See also ], ''The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte'', Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1987; Chapter 9, "Schulze's Skepticism".</ref> gave rise to a robust discussion of skepticism in ]ic philosophy, especially by ].<ref>See (1) H. S. Harris, "Skepticism, Dogmatism and Speculation in the Critical Journal" (1985), in ''Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism'', Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 2000; (2) G. W. F. Hegel, "On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy, Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One", Translated by H. S. Harris, in di Giovanni and Harris (2000) (cited just above); and (3) Michael N. Forster, ''Hegel and Skepticism'', Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1989.</ref> Kant's idea was that the real world (the '']'' or thing-in-itself) was inaccessible to human reason (though the empirical world of nature can be known to human understanding) and therefore we can never know anything about the ultimate reality of the world. Hegel argued against Kant that although Kant was right that using what Hegel called "finite" concepts of "the understanding" precluded knowledge of reality, we were not constrained to use only "finite" concepts and could actually acquire knowledge of reality using "infinite concepts" that arise from self-consciousness.<ref>Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, '']'' (1830), § 28, pp. 65–68, Translated by T. F. Garaets, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 1991.</ref> | |||
A fractal represents existence. | |||
=== Skepticism in the 20th century and contemporary philosophy === | |||
Integration is a conceptual method by which the sum of an infinite system can be defined. | |||
] famously presented the "]" argument against skepticism in his 1925 paper, "]".<ref name="SEP Skepticism"/> Moore claimed that he could prove that the external world exists by simply presenting the following argument while holding up his hands: "Here is one hand; here is another hand; therefore, there are at least two objects; therefore, external-world skepticism fails". His argument was developed for the purpose of vindicating ] and refuting skepticism.<ref name="SEP Skepticism"/> ] later argued in his '']'' (posthumously published in 1969) that Moore's argument rested on the way that ordinary language is used, rather than on anything about knowledge.<ref>], Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative, in: ''Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition'', António Marques & Rui Bertrand Romao (Eds.), Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Wien: Peter Lang, 2020, pp. 113–122. {{ISBN|978-3-0343-1595-1}}.</ref> | |||
In contemporary philosophy, ] was a particularly influential scholar on the topic of skepticism. His account of the history of skepticism given in ''The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle'' (first edition published as ''The History of Scepticism From Erasmus to Descartes'') was accepted as the standard for contemporary scholarship in the area for decades after its release in 1960.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Sublimity and skepticism in Montaigne and Milton|last=Sedley|first= David Louis|date=2005|publisher=University of Michigan Press|isbn=978-0-472-11528-0|location=Ann Arbor|oclc=60715259}}</ref> ] also published a number of works on philosophical skepticism, most notably his 1984 monograph, ''The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism''.<ref>{{cite journal |title=The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism |url=https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/0198247613.001.0001/acprof-9780198247616 |website=Oxford University Press |year=1984 |doi=10.1093/0198247613.001.0001 |access-date=11 August 2020|last1=Stroud |first1=Barry |isbn=978-0-19-824761-6 }}</ref> From the mid-1990s, Stroud, alongside ], put forward influential anti-externalist arguments in favour of a position called "metaepistemological scepticism".<ref>{{Cite book|last1=Pritchard|first1=Duncan|title=Intellectual Assurance: Essays on Traditional Epistemic Internalism|last2=Ranalli|first2=Chris|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=2016|editor-last=Bergmann|editor-first=Michael|editor-link=Michael Bergmann (philosopher)|chapter=On Metaepistemological Scepticism|author-link=Duncan Pritchard|editor-last2=Coppenger|editor-first2=Brett|chapter-url=https://philpapers.org/rec/RANOMS}}</ref> Other contemporary philosophers known for their work on skepticism include ], ], and ].<ref name="SEP Skepticism"/> | |||
Let us define X = Laplacian on a fractal | |||
== History of skepticism in non-Western philosophy == | |||
Let us define Existence as the integral of X, from -8 to +8. | |||
The integration of a fractal is 0. | |||
=== Ancient Indian skepticism === | |||
Existence = 0. | |||
<!--"Maudgalyayana#Meeting the Buddha" links here.--> | |||
], common in Buddhism and Jainism.]] | |||
====Ajñana==== | |||
Let us define a thing as a set which may or may not have subsets relative to itself. | |||
{{main|Ajñana}} | |||
Ajñana (literally 'non-knowledge') were the skeptical school of ancient Indian philosophy. It was a ] movement and a major rival of early Buddhism and Jainism. They have been recorded in Buddhist and Jain texts. They held that it was impossible to obtain knowledge of metaphysical nature or ascertain the truth value of philosophical propositions; and even if knowledge was possible, it was useless and disadvantageous for final salvation. | |||
====Buddhism==== | |||
A thing may have supersets relative to itself or sister sets relative to itself. | |||
{{main|Buddhist philosophy}} | |||
The historical Buddha asserted certain doctrines as true, such as the possibility of ]; however, he also upheld a form of skepticism with regards to ] (''avyākata'') and some he saw as "incomprehensible" ('']''). Because the Buddha saw these questions (which tend to be of metaphysical topics) as unhelpful on the path and merely leading to confusion and "a thicket of views", he promoted ] towards them. This allowed him to carve out an epistemic middle way between what he saw as the extremes of claiming absolute objectivity (associated with the claims to omniscience of the Jain ]) and extreme skepticism (associated with the Ajñana thinker ]).<ref>Kalupahana, David J. A History of Buddhist Philosophy: Continuities and Discontinuities, page 21.</ref> | |||
Later ] remained highly skeptical of Indian metaphysical arguments. The Buddhist philosopher ] in particular has been seen as the founder of the ], which has been in turn compared with Greek Skepticism. Nagarjuna's statement that he has "no thesis" (''pratijña'') has parallels in the statements of ] of having "no position".<ref>The Cowherds. Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2011, pp. 115–116.</ref> Nagarjuna famously opens his magnum opus, the ''Mulamadhyamakakarika'', with the statement that the Buddha claimed that true happiness was found through dispelling 'vain thinking' (], also "conceptual proliferation").<ref>Hayes, Richard P. Dignāga on the interpretation of signs, page 53.</ref> | |||
Let us define something as a thing with subsets relative to itself. | |||
According to Richard P. Hayes, the Buddhist philosopher ] is also a kind of skeptic, which is in line with most early ]. Hayes writes: | |||
Let us define nothing as a thing without subsets relative to itself. | |||
<blockquote>...in both early Buddhism and in the Skeptics one can find the view put forward that man's pursuit of happiness, the highest good, is obstructed by his tenacity in holding ungrounded and unnecessary opinions about all manner of things. Much of Buddhist philosophy, I shall argue, can be seen as an attempt to break this habit of holding on to opinions.<ref>Hayes, Richard P. Dignāga on the interpretation of signs, page 35.</ref></blockquote> | |||
A thing, by definition, can choice to be nothing or something. | |||
Scholars like Adrian Kuzminski have argued that ] (ca. 365–270) might have been influenced by Indian Buddhists during his journey with ].<ref>Kuzminski, Adrian. Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism (Studies in Comparative Philosophy and Religion), 2008.</ref> | |||
Choice, by definition, is random. | |||
====Cārvāka philosophy==== | |||
Nothing = 0. | |||
{{main|Cārvāka}} | |||
The ] (Sanskrit: चार्वाक) school of ], also known as Lokāyata, is a classically cited (but historically disputed) school of ancient Indian philosophy. While no texts or authoritative doctrine have survived, followers of this system are frequently mentioned in philosophical treatises of other schools, often as an initial counterpoint against which to assert their own arguments. | |||
Something <> 0. | |||
Cārvāka is classified as a "heterodox" (nāstika) system, characterized as a materialistic and atheistic school of thought. This school was also known for being strongly skeptical of the claims of ], such as ] and ]. | |||
Existence = 0. | |||
====Jainism==== | |||
Existence = Nothing. | |||
{{Main|Anekantavada|Syadvada}} | |||
While Jain philosophy claims that is it possible to achieve ], absolute knowledge (]), at the moment of enlightenment, their theory of ] or 'many sided-ness', also known as the principle of relative ], allows for a practical form of skeptical thought regarding philosophical and religious doctrines (for un-enlightened beings, not all-knowing ]). | |||
According to this theory, the truth or the reality is perceived differently from different points of view, and that no single point of view is the complete truth.<ref>{{cite book | last =Dundas | first =Paul | title =The Jains | publisher =Routledge | year =2002 | location =London | isbn =978-0-415-26606-2 }}</ref><ref name=koller/> Jain doctrine states that, an object has infinite modes of existence and qualities and, as such, they cannot be completely perceived in all its aspects and manifestations, due to inherent limitations of the humans. Anekāntavāda is literally the doctrine of non-onesidedness or manifoldness; it is often translated as "non-absolutism". ] is the theory of conditioned predication which provides an expression to anekānta by recommending that epithet "Syād" be attached to every expression.<ref>{{cite book | last =Chatterjea | first =Tara | title =Knowledge and Freedom in Indian Philosophy | publisher =Lexington Books | year =2001 | location =Lanham, MD | isbn =978-0-7391-0692-1 |pages= 77–87}}</ref> Syādvāda is not only an extension of Anekānta ], but a separate system of logic capable of standing on its own force. As reality is complex, no single proposition can express the nature of reality fully. Thus the term "syāt" should be prefixed before each proposition giving it a conditional point of view and thus removing any dogmatism in the statement.<ref name=koller>{{cite journal | last =Koller | first =John M. | title =Syādvāda as the epistemological key to the Jaina middle way metaphysics of Anekāntavāda | journal =Philosophy East and West | volume = 50 | issue = 3 | pages =400–407| jstor=1400182 |date=July 2000 | issn =0031-8221 | id ={{ProQuest|216882163}} }}</ref> For Jains, fully enlightened beings are able to see reality from all sides and thus have ultimate knowledge of all things. This idea of omniscience was criticized by Buddhists such as ]. | |||
Nothing->Something->Nothing | |||
=== Ancient Chinese philosophy === | |||
Nothing can come from Something; Something can come from Nothing. | |||
] | |||
==== Zhuang Zhou (c. 369 – c. 286 BCE) ==== | |||
A thing is infinite possibility. | |||
] (莊子,"Master Zhuang") was a famous ancient Chinese ] philosopher during the ] period. Zhuang Zhou demonstrated his skeptical thinking through several anecdotes in the preeminent work ] attributed to him: | |||
* "The Debate on the Joy of Fish" (知魚之樂) : In this anecdote, Zhuang Zhou argued with his fellow philosopher ] whether they knew the fish in the pond were happy or not, and Zhuang Zhou made the famous observation that "You are not I. How do you know that I do not know that the fish are happy?" <ref name=":02">{{Cite book |title=The Complete works of Zhuangzi|last=Zhuangzi|translator=Watson, Burton|year=2017 |orig-date=2013 |isbn=978-0-231-16474-0|location=New York |publisher=Columbia University Press |oclc=826640070 }}</ref> (Autumn Floods 秋水篇, Zhuangzi) | |||
* "The Butterfly of the Dream"(周公夢蝶) : The paradox of "Butterfly Dream" described Zhuang Zhou's confusion after dreaming himself to be a butterfly: "But he didn't know if he was Zhuang Zhou who had dreamt he was a butterfly, or a butterfly dreaming that he was Zhuang Zhou."<ref name=":02" /> (Discussion on Making All Things Equal 齊物篇, Zhuangzi) | |||
Through these anecdotes in Zhuangzi, Zhuang Zhou indicated his belief in the limitation of language and human communication and the inaccessibility of universal truth. This establishes him as a skeptic. But he was by no means a radical skeptic: he only applied skeptical methods partially, in arguments demonstrating his Taoist beliefs. He held the Taoist beliefs themselves dogmatically.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Berthel|first=Ken|date=2015-12-01|title=Language in Zhuangzi: A Theme that Reveals the Nature of its Relativism and Skepticism|journal=Journal of Chinese Philosophy|language=en|volume=42|pages=562–576|doi=10.1111/1540-6253.12215|issn=1540-6253}}</ref> | |||
==== Wang Chong (27 – {{circa|100|lk=no}} CE) ==== | |||
From nothing can come something, if so chosen. | |||
] ({{lang|zh|王充}}) was the leading figure of the skeptic branch of the ] school in China during the first century CE. He introduced a method of rational critique and applied it to the widespread dogmatism thinking of his age like ] (the main contemporary Confucianism ideology that linked all natural phenomena with human ethics), state-led cults, and popular superstition. His own philosophy incorporated both ] and ] thinkings, and it was based on a secular, rational practice of developing hypotheses based on natural events to explain the universe which exemplified a form of ] that resembled the philosophical idea of ] like ].<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Xuerong|first=Ouyang|date=December 2003|title=略论王充的怀疑主义|journal=Journal of Kaifeng University|volume=17-04|pages=11–13}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|title=The shorter Science and civilisation in China: an abridgement of Joseph Needham's original text|last=Needham|first= Joseph|date=1978|publisher=Cambridge University Press|others=Ronan, Colin A.|isbn=978-0-521-23582-2|location=Cambridge|oclc=3345021}}</ref> | |||
=== Medieval Islamic philosophy === | |||
From something can come something, if so chosen. | |||
'']'', written by the scholar ] (1058–1111), marks a major turn in Islamic ]. His encounter with skepticism led Ghazali to embrace a form of theological ], or the belief that all causal events and interactions are not the product of material conjunctions but rather the immediate and present will of God. {{citation needed |date=April 2022}} | |||
In the ] Ghazali wrote towards the end of his life, ''The Deliverance From Error'' (''Al-munqidh min al-ḍalāl'' <ref>Annotated translations by Richard Joseph McCarthy (''Freedom and Fulfillment'', Boston: Twayne, 1980; ''Deliverance From Error'', Louisville, Ky.: Fons Vitae, 1999) and George F. McLean (''Deliverance from error and mystical union with the Almighty'', Washington, D.C.: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy, 2001). An earlier translation by ] was first published in 1953 (''The faith and practice of al-Ghazālī'', London: G. Allen and Unwin).</ref>), Ghazali recounts how, once a crisis of epistemological skepticism was resolved by "a light which God Most High cast into my breast...the key to most knowledge",<ref>McCarthy 1980, p. 66</ref> he studied and mastered the arguments of ], Islamic philosophy, and ]. Though appreciating what was valid in the first two of these, at least, he determined that all three approaches were inadequate and found ultimate value only in the mystical experience and spiritual insight he attained as a result of following ] practices. ], in '']'', considered the autobiography an important document for "the purely literary student who would like to become acquainted with the inwardness of religions other than the Christian", comparing it to recorded personal religious confessions and autobiographical literature in the Christian tradition.<ref>William James, ''Varieties of Religious Experience'', Harvard University Press, 1985, p. 319 .</ref> | |||
Nothing can be predicted. | |||
=== Aztec philosophy === | |||
Nothing is the beginning. | |||
Recordings of ] suggest that the elite classes believed in an essentially ] worldview, in which ] represents a unified, underlying universal force. Human beings cannot truly perceive teotl due to its chaotic, constantly changing nature, just the "masks"/facets it is manifested as.<ref name="iepMaffie">{{cite web|author=James Maffie|title=Aztec Philosophy|website= ]|date= 2005|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/a/aztec.htm }}</ref><ref>James Maffie (2014). ''Aztec Philosophy: Understanding a World in Motion''. University Press of Colorado {{Page?|date=August 2022}}{{ISBN?}}</ref> | |||
Nothing is the end. | |||
God is Nothing. | |||
God is the Beginning and the End. | |||
God is Everything. | |||
I am within the set of Everything. | |||
I am within the set of God. | |||
I am Something. | |||
God is Everything. | |||
I am God. | |||
-EAH | |||
==References== | |||
<references /> | |||
== Further reading == | |||
* ]; Reichel, Oswald J., , Longmans, Green, and Co., 1892 | |||
==See also== | ==See also== | ||
{{columns-list|* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | |||
* ] - a response to skepticism | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] | |||
* ] | * ] | ||
* ] (opposite of skepticism) | |||
* ] | |||
* ]}} | |||
==References== | |||
{{Reflist}} | |||
== Further reading == | |||
* ] 2003. ''The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle''. New York: Oxford University Press. | |||
* ] and J. R. Maia Neto, eds. 2007. ''Skepticism: An Anthology''. New York: Prometheus Books. | |||
* ] 1987. ''The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte''. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. | |||
* Breker, Christian. 2011. ''Einführender Kommentar zu Sextus Empiricus' "Grundriss der pyrrhonischen Skepsis"'', Mainz, 2011: electr. publication, University of Mainz. (comment on Sextus Empiricus' "Outlines of Pyrrhonism" in German language) | |||
* di Giovanni, George and H. S. Harris, eds. 2000. ''Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism''. Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing. | |||
* Forster, Michael N. 1989. ''Hegel and Skepticism''. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. | |||
* Harris, H. S. 1985. "Skepticism, Dogmatism and Speculation in the ''Critical Journal''". In di Giovanni and Harris 2000. | |||
* ]. 1802. "On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy, Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One". Translated by H. S. Harris. In di Giovanni and Harris 2000. | |||
* Leavitt, Fred. 2021. "If Ignorance is Bliss We Should All be Ecstatic." Open Books. | |||
* ], 1971. "Why Not Scepticism?" ''Philosophical Forum'', vol. II, pp. 283-298. | |||
* ], Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative, in: ''Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition'', António Marques & Rui Bertrand Romao (Eds.), Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Wien: Peter Lang, 2020, pp. 113–122. | |||
* François-Xavier de Peretti, « Stop Doubting with Descartes », dans M. Garcia-Valdecasas, J. Milburn, J.-B. Guillon (éds.), « Anti-skepticism », Topoi. An International Review of Philosophy, Springer Nature, on line 3.11.2022 | |||
* François-Xavier de Peretti, « Descartes sceptique malgré lui ? », International Journal for the Study of Skepticism, 11 (3), 2021, Brill, Leyde, pp. 177-192. Online publication date: 15 octobre 2020. Doi:https://doi.org/10.1163/22105700-bja10016 | |||
* Thorsrud, Harald. 2009. ''Ancient Scepticism''. Berkeley: University of California Press. | |||
* ]. 1975. ''Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism''. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. 2002. | |||
* ] and Oswald J. Reichel. 1892. . London: Longmans, Green, and Co. | |||
==External links== | ==External links== | ||
* {{cite SEP |url-id=skepticism |title=Skepticism |last=Klein |first=Peter}} | |||
* | |||
* entry in the ] | |||
* | |||
* entry in the ] | |||
* {{sep entry|skepticism|Skepticism}} | |||
* entry in the ] | |||
* On-line version of two recently published books by philosopher ] (in ]) | |||
* by Keith DeRose | |||
* by Stephen Novella MD, The New England Journal of Skepticism | |||
* by |
* by Stephen Novella MD, The New England Journal of Skepticism | ||
* by Peter Suber | |||
* | |||
* by ] | |||
* {{cite news | title = Wall-to-wall impeachment coverage is not changing any minds. Here's how journalists can reach the undecided | first = Margaret | last = Sullivan | date = 2019-12-05 | newspaper = ] | quote = Columnist Michelle Goldberg of the New York Times offered a name Wednesday for one aspect of what's happening before our eyes. Responding to the absurd statement of Rep. Douglas A. Collins (R-Ga.) — "there are no set facts here" — she said it summed up the long-term Republican strategy: "epistemological nihilism." | url = https://www.washingtonpost.com/lifestyle/style/wall-to-wall-impeachment-coverage-is-not-changing-any-minds-heres-how-journalists-can-reach-the-undecided/2019/12/05/a04aa658-16c3-11ea-a659-7d69641c6ff7_story.html}} | |||
{{Skepticism}} | {{Skepticism}} | ||
{{Philosophy topics}} | {{Philosophy topics}} | ||
{{Portal bar|Philosophy|Psychology}} | |||
] | ] | ||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Latest revision as of 09:46, 2 November 2024
Philosophical views that question the possibility of knowledge or certainty For a more general discussion of skepticism, see Skepticism.
Part of a series on |
Epistemology |
---|
Schools |
Concepts |
Domains |
Epistemologists |
Related fields |
Philosophical skepticism (UK spelling: scepticism; from Greek σκέψις skepsis, "inquiry") is a family of philosophical views that question the possibility of knowledge. It differs from other forms of skepticism in that it even rejects very plausible knowledge claims that belong to basic common sense. Philosophical skeptics are often classified into two general categories: Those who deny all possibility of knowledge, and those who advocate for the suspension of judgment due to the inadequacy of evidence. This distinction is modeled after the differences between the Academic skeptics and the Pyrrhonian skeptics in ancient Greek philosophy. Pyrrhonian skepticism is a practice of suspending judgement, and skepticism in this sense is understood as a way of life that helps the practitioner achieve inner peace. Some types of philosophical skepticism reject all forms of knowledge while others limit this rejection to certain fields, for example, knowledge about moral doctrines or about the external world. Some theorists criticize philosophical skepticism based on the claim that it is a self-refuting idea since its proponents seem to claim to know that there is no knowledge. Other objections focus on its implausibility and distance from regular life.
Overview
This section needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (July 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
Philosophical skepticism is a doubtful attitude toward commonly accepted knowledge claims. It is an important form of skepticism. Skepticism in general is a questioning attitude toward all kinds of knowledge claims. In this wide sense, it is quite common in everyday life: many people are ordinary skeptics about parapsychology or about astrology because they doubt the claims made by proponents of these fields. But the same people are not skeptical about other knowledge claims like the ones found in regular school books. Philosophical skepticism differs from ordinary skepticism in that it even rejects knowledge claims that belong to basic common sense and seem to be very certain. For this reason, it is sometimes referred to as radical doubt. In some cases, it is even proclaimed that one does not know that "I have two hands" or that "the sun will come out tomorrow". In this regard, philosophical skepticism is not a position commonly adopted by regular people in everyday life. This denial of knowledge is usually associated with the demand that one should suspend one's beliefs about the doubted proposition. This means that one should neither believe nor disbelieve it but keep an open mind without committing oneself one way or the other. Philosophical skepticism is often based on the idea that no matter how certain one is about a given belief, one could still be wrong about it. From this observation, it is argued that the belief does not amount to knowledge. Philosophical skepticism follows from the consideration that this might be the case for most or all beliefs. Because of its wide-ranging consequences, it is of central interest to theories of knowledge since it questions their very foundations.
According to some definitions, philosophical skepticism is not just the rejection of some forms of commonly accepted knowledge but the rejection of all forms of knowledge. In this regard, we may have relatively secure beliefs in some cases but these beliefs never amount to knowledge. Weaker forms of philosophical skepticism restrict this rejection to specific fields, like the external world or moral doctrines. In some cases, knowledge per se is not rejected but it is still denied that one can ever be absolutely certain.
There are only few defenders of philosophical skepticism in the strong sense. In this regard, it is much more commonly used as a theoretical tool to test theories. On this view, it is a philosophical methodology that can be utilized to probe a theory to find its weak points, either to expose it or to modify it in order to arrive at a better version of it. However, some theorists distinguish philosophical skepticism from methodological skepticism in that philosophical skepticism is an approach that questions the possibility of certainty in knowledge, whereas methodological skepticism is an approach that subjects all knowledge claims to scrutiny with the goal of sorting out true from false claims. Similarly, scientific skepticism differs from philosophical skepticism in that scientific skepticism is an epistemological position in which one questions the veracity of claims lacking empirical evidence. In practice, the term most commonly references the examination of claims and theories that appear to be pseudoscience, rather than the routine discussions and challenges among scientists.
In ancient philosophy, skepticism was seen not just as a theory about the existence of knowledge but as a way of life. This outlook is motivated by the idea that suspending one's judgment on all kinds of issues brings with it inner peace and thereby contributes to the skeptic's happiness.
Classification
Skepticism can be classified according to its scope. Local skepticism involves being skeptical about particular areas of knowledge (e.g. moral skepticism, skepticism about the external world, or skepticism about other minds), whereas radical skepticism claims that one cannot know anything—including that one cannot know about knowing anything.
Skepticism can also be classified according to its method. Western philosophy has two basic approaches to skepticism. Cartesian skepticism—named somewhat misleadingly after René Descartes, who was not a skeptic but used some traditional skeptical arguments in his Meditations to help establish his rationalist approach to knowledge—attempts to show that any proposed knowledge claim can be doubted. Agrippan skepticism focuses on justification rather than the possibility of doubt. According to this view, none of the ways in which one might attempt to justify a claim are adequate. One can justify a claim based on other claims, but this leads to an infinite regress of justifications. One can use a dogmatic assertion, but this is not a justification. One can use circular reasoning, but this fails to justify the conclusion.
Skeptical scenarios
A skeptical scenario is a hypothetical situation which can be used in an argument for skepticism about a particular claim or class of claims. Usually the scenario posits the existence of a deceptive power that deceives our senses and undermines the justification of knowledge otherwise accepted as justified, and is proposed in order to call into question our ordinary claims to knowledge on the grounds that we cannot exclude the possibility of skeptical scenarios being true. Skeptical scenarios have received a great deal of attention in modern Western philosophy.
The first major skeptical scenario in modern Western philosophy appears in René Descartes' Meditations on First Philosophy. At the end of the first Meditation Descartes writes: "I will suppose... that some evil demon of the utmost power and cunning has employed all his energies to deceive me."
- The "evil demon problem", also known as "Descartes' evil demon", was first proposed by René Descartes. It invokes the possibility of a being who could deliberately mislead one into falsely believing everything that you take to be true.
- The "brain in a vat" hypothesis is cast in contemporary scientific terms. It supposes that one might be a disembodied brain kept alive in a vat and fed false sensory signals by a mad scientist. Further, it asserts that since a brain in a vat would have no way of knowing that it was a brain in a vat, you cannot prove that you are not a brain in a vat.
- The "dream argument", proposed by both René Descartes and Zhuangzi, supposes reality to be indistinguishable from a dream.
- The "five minute hypothesis", most notably proposed by Bertrand Russell, suggests that we cannot prove that the world was not created five minutes ago (along with false memories and false evidence suggesting that it was not only five minutes old).
- The "simulated reality hypothesis" or "Matrix hypothesis" suggests that everyone, or even the entire universe, might be inside a computer simulation or virtual reality.
- The "Solipsistic" theory that claims that knowledge of the world is an illusion of the Self.
Epistemological skepticism
Skepticism, as an epistemological view, calls into question whether knowledge is possible at all. This is distinct from other known skeptical practices, including Cartesian skepticism, as it targets knowledge in general instead of individual types of knowledge.
Skeptics argue that belief in something does not justify an assertion of knowledge of it. In this, skeptics oppose foundationalism, which states that there are basic positions that are self-justified or beyond justification, without reference to others. (One example of such foundationalism may be found in Spinoza's Ethics.)
Among other arguments, skeptics use the Münchhausen trilemma and the problem of the criterion to claim that no certain belief can be achieved. This position is known as "global skepticism" or "radical skepticism." Foundationalists have used the same trilemma as a justification for demanding the validity of basic beliefs. Epistemological nihilism rejects the possibility of human knowledge, but not necessarily knowledge in general.
There are two different categories of epistemological skepticism, which can be referred to as mitigated and unmitigated skepticism. The two forms are contrasting but are still true forms of skepticism. Mitigated skepticism does not accept "strong" or "strict" knowledge claims but does, however, approve specific weaker ones. These weaker claims can be assigned the title of "virtual knowledge", but must be to justified belief. Some mitigated skeptics are also fallibilists, arguing that knowledge does not require certainty. Mitigated skeptics hold that knowledge does not require certainty and that many beliefs are, in practice, certain to the point that they can be safely acted upon in order to live significant and meaningful lives. Unmitigated skepticism rejects both claims of virtual knowledge and strong knowledge. Characterising knowledge as strong, weak, virtual or genuine can be determined differently depending on a person's viewpoint as well as their characterisation of knowledge. Unmitigated skeptics believe that objective truths are unknowable and that man should live in an isolated environment in order to win mental peace. This is because everything, according to them, is changing and relative. The refusal to make judgments is of uttermost importance since there is no knowledge; only probable opinions.
Criticism
Philosophical skepticism has been criticized in various ways. Some criticisms see it as a self-refuting idea while others point out that it is implausible, psychologically impossible, or a pointless intellectual game. This position is based on the idea that philosophical skepticism not only rejects the existence of knowledge but seems to make knowledge claims itself at the same time. For example, to claim that there is no knowledge seems to be itself a knowledge claim. This problem is particularly relevant for versions of philosophical skepticism that deny any form of knowledge. So the global skeptic denies that any claim is rationally justified but then goes on to provide arguments in an attempt to rationally justify their denial. Some philosophical skeptics have responded to this objection by restricting the denial of knowledge to certain fields without denying the existence of knowledge in general. Another defense consists in understanding philosophical skepticism not as a theory but as a tool or a methodology. In this case, it may be used fruitfully to reject and improve philosophical systems despite its shortcomings as a theory.
Another criticism holds that philosophical skepticism is highly counterintuitive by pointing out how far removed it is from regular life. For example, it seems very impractical, if not psychologically impossible, to suspend all beliefs at the same time. And even if it were possible, it would not be advisable since "the complete skeptic would wind up starving to death or walking into walls or out of windows". This criticism can allow that there are some arguments that support philosophical skepticism. However, it has been claimed that they are not nearly strong enough to support such a radical conclusion. Common-sense philosophers follow this line of thought by arguing that regular common-sense beliefs are much more reliable than the skeptics' intricate arguments. George Edward Moore, for example, tried to refute skepticism about the existence of the external world, not by engaging with its complex arguments, but by using a simple observation: that he has two hands. For Moore, this observation is a reliable source of knowledge incompatible with external world skepticism since it entails that at least two physical objects exist.
A closely related objection sees philosophical skepticism as an "idle academic exercise" or a "waste of time". This is often based on the idea that, because of its initial implausibility and distance from everyday life, it has little or no practical value. In this regard, Arthur Schopenhauer compares the position of radical skepticism to a border fortress that is best ignored: it is impregnable but its garrison does not pose any threat since it never sets foot outside the fortress. One defense of philosophical skepticism is that it has had important impacts on the history of philosophy at large and not just among skeptical philosophers. This is due to its critical attitude, which remains a constant challenge to the epistemic foundations of various philosophical theories. It has often provoked creative responses from other philosophers when trying to modify the affected theory to avoid the problem of skepticism.
According to Pierre Le Morvan, there are two very common negative responses to philosophical skepticism. The first understands it as a threat to all kinds of philosophical theories and strives to disprove it. According to the second, philosophical skepticism is a useless distraction and should better be avoided altogether. Le Morvan himself proposes a positive third alternative: to use it as a philosophical tool in a few selected cases to overcome prejudices and foster practical wisdom.
History of Western skepticism
Ancient Greek skepticism
Part of a series on |
Pyrrhonism |
---|
Pyrrhonists |
Concepts |
Similar philosophies |
Modern influence |
Philosophy portal |
Ancient Greek skeptics were not "skeptics" in the contemporary sense of selective, localized doubt. Their concerns were epistemological, noting that truth claims could not be adequately supported, and psychotherapeutic, noting that beliefs caused mental perturbation.
The Western tradition of systematic skepticism goes back at least as far as Pyrrho of Elis (b. c. 360 BCE) and arguably to Xenophanes (b. c. 570 BCE). Parts of skepticism also appear among the "5th century sophists develop forms of debate which are ancestors of skeptical argumentation. They take pride in arguing in a persuasive fashion for both sides of an issue."
In Hellenistic philosophy, Pyrrhonism and Academic Skepticism were the two schools of skeptical philosophy. Subsequently, the words Academic and Pyrrhonist were often used to mean skeptic.
Pyrrhonism
Main article: PyrrhonismLike other Hellenistic philosophies, the goal of Pyrrhonism was eudaimonia, which the Pyrrhonists sought through achieving ataraxia (an untroubled state of mind), which they found could be induced by producing a state of epoché (suspension of judgment) regarding non-evident matters. Epoché could be produced by pitting one dogma against another to undermine belief, and by questioning whether a belief could be justified. In support of this questioning Pyrrhonists developed the skeptical arguments cited above (the Ten Modes of Aenesidemus and the Five Modes of Agrippa) demonstrating that beliefs cannot be justified:
Pyrrho of Elis
Main article: PyrrhoAccording to an account of Pyrrho's life by his student Timon of Phlius, Pyrrho extolled a way to become happy and tranquil:
'The things themselves are equally indifferent, and unstable, and indeterminate, and therefore neither our senses nor our opinions are either true or false. For this reason then we must not trust them, but be without opinions, and without bias, and without wavering, saying of every single thing that it no more is than is not, or both is and is not, or neither is nor is not.
Aenesidemus
Main article: AenesidemusPyrrhonism faded as a movement following the death of Pyrrho's student Timon. The Academy became slowly more dogmatic such that in the first century BCE Aenesidemus denounced the Academics as "Stoics fighting against Stoics", breaking with the Academy to revive Pyrrhonism. Aenesidemus's best known contribution to skepticism was his now-lost book, Pyrrhonian Discourses, which is only known to us through Photius, Sextus Empiricus, and to a lesser extent Diogenes Laërtius. The skeptical arguments most closely associated with Aenesidemus are the ten modes described above designed to induce epoche.
Sextus Empiricus
Main article: Sextus EmpiricusThe works of Sextus Empiricus (c. 200 CE) are the main surviving account of ancient Pyrrhonism. Long before Sextus' time, the Academy had abandoned skepticism and had been destroyed as a formal institution. Sextus compiled and further developed the Pyrrhonists' skeptical arguments, most of which were directed against the Stoics but included arguments against all of the schools of Hellenistic philosophy, including the Academic skeptics.
Sextus, as the most systematic author of the works by Hellenistic skeptics which have survived, noted that there are at least ten modes of skepticism. These modes may be broken down into three categories: one may be skeptical of the subjective perceiver, of the objective world, and the relation between perceiver and the world. His arguments are as follows.
Subjectively, the powers of the senses and reasoning may vary among different people. And since knowledge is a product of one or the other, and since neither are reliable, knowledge would seem to be in trouble. For instance, a color-blind person sees the world quite differently from everyone else. Moreover, one cannot even give preference based on the power of reason, i.e., by treating the rational animal as a carrier of greater knowledge than the irrational animal, since the irrational animal is still adept at navigating their environment, which suggests the ability to "know" about some aspects of the environment.
Secondly, the personality of the individual might also influence what they observe, since (it is argued) preferences are based on sense-impressions, differences in preferences can be attributed to differences in the way that people are affected by the object. (Empiricus:56)
Third, the perceptions of each individual sense seemingly have nothing in common with the other senses: i.e., the color "red" has little to do with the feeling of touching a red object. This is manifest when our senses "disagree" with each other: for example, a mirage presents certain visible features, but is not responsive to any other kind of sense. In that case, our other senses defeat the impressions of sight. But one may also be lacking enough powers of sense to understand the world in its entirety: if one had an extra sense, then one might know of things in a way that the present five senses are unable to advise us of. Given that our senses can be shown to be unreliable by appealing to other senses, and so our senses may be incomplete (relative to some more perfect sense that one lacks), then it follows that all of our senses may be unreliable. (Empiricus:58)
Fourth, our circumstances when one perceives anything may be either natural or unnatural, i.e., one may be either in a state of wakefulness or sleep. But it is entirely possible that things in the world really are exactly as they appear to be to those in unnatural states (i.e., if everything were an elaborate dream). (Empiricus:59)
One can have reasons for doubt that are based on the relationship between objective "facts" and subjective experience. The positions, distances, and places of objects would seem to affect how they are perceived by the person: for instance, the portico may appear tapered when viewed from one end, but symmetrical when viewed at the other; and these features are different. Because they are different features, to believe the object has both properties at the same time is to believe it has two contradictory properties. Since this is absurd, one must suspend judgment about what properties it possesses due to the contradictory experiences. (Empiricus:63)
One may also observe that the things one perceives are, in a sense, polluted by experience. Any given perception—say, of a chair—will always be perceived within some context or other (i.e., next to a table, on a mat, etc.) Since this is the case, one often only speaks of ideas as they occur in the context of the other things that are paired with it, and therefore, one can never know of the true nature of the thing, but only how it appears to us in context. (Empiricus: 64)
Along the same lines, the skeptic may insist that all things are relative, by arguing that:
- Absolute appearances either differ from relative appearances, or they do not.
- If absolutes do not differ from relatives, then they are themselves relative.
- But if absolutes do differ from relatives, then they are relative, because all things that differ must differ from something; and to "differ" from something is to be relative to something. (Empiricus:67)
Finally, one has reason to disbelieve that one knows anything by looking at problems in understanding objects by themselves. Things, when taken individually, may appear to be very different from when they are in mass quantities: for instance, the shavings of a goat's horn are white when taken alone, yet the horn intact is black.
Skeptical arguments
The ancient Greek Pyrrhonists developed sets of arguments to demonstrate that claims about reality cannot be adequately justified. Two sets of these arguments are well known. The oldest set is known as the ten tropes of Aenesidemus—although whether he invented the tropes or just systematized them from prior Pyrrhonist works is unknown. The tropes represent reasons for epoché (suspension of judgment). These are as follows:
- Different animals manifest different modes of perception;
- Similar differences are seen among individual men;
- For the same man, information perceived with the senses is self-contradictory
- Furthermore, it varies from time to time with physical changes
- In addition, this data differs according to local relations
- Objects are known only indirectly through the medium of air, moisture, etc.
- These objects are in a condition of perpetual change in color, temperature, size and motion
- All perceptions are relative and interact one upon another
- Our impressions become less critical through repetition and custom
- All men are brought up with different beliefs, under different laws and social conditions
Another set are known as the five tropes of Agrippa:
- Dissent – The uncertainty demonstrated by the differences of opinions among philosophers and people in general.
- Progress ad infinitum – All proof rests on matters themselves in need of proof, and so on to infinity, i.e, the regress argument.
- Relation – All things are changed as their relations become changed, or, as we look upon them from different points of view.
- Assumption – The truth asserted is based on an unsupported assumption.
- Circularity – The truth asserted involves a circularity of proofs.
According to Victor Brochard "the five tropes can be regarded as the most radical and most precise formulation of philosophical skepticism that has ever been given. In a sense, they are still irresistible today."
Academic skepticism
Main article: Academic skepticismPyrrho's thinking subsequently influenced the Platonic Academy, arising first in the Academic skepticism of the Middle Academy under Arcesilaus (c. 315 – 241 BCE) and then the New Academy under Carneades (c. 213–129 BCE). Clitomachus, a student of Carneades, interpreted his teacher's philosophy as suggesting an account of knowledge based on truth-likeness. The Roman politician and philosopher, Cicero, was also an adherent of the skepticism of the New Academy, even though a return to a more dogmatic orientation of the school was already beginning to take place.
Augustine on skepticism
In 386 CE, Augustine published Contra Academicos (Against the Academic Skeptics), which argued against claims made by the Academic Skeptics (266–90 BCE) on the following grounds:
- Objection from Error: Through logic, Augustine argues that philosophical skepticism does not lead to happiness like the Academic Skeptics claim. His arguments is summarized as:
- A wise man lives according to reason, and thus is able to be happy.
- One who is searching for knowledge but never finds it is in error.
- Imperfection objection: People in error are not happy, because being in error is an imperfection, and people cannot be happy with an imperfection.
- Conclusion: One who is still seeking knowledge cannot be happy.
- Error of Non-Assent: Augustine's argument that suspending belief does not fully prevent one from error. His argument is summarized below.
- Introduction of the error: Let P be true. If a person fails to believe P due to suspension of belief in order to avoid error, the person is also committing an error.
- The Anecdote of the Two Travelers: Travelers A and B are trying to reach the same destination. At a fork in the road, a poor shepherd tells them to go left. Traveler A immediately believes him and reaches the correct destination. Traveler B suspends belief, and instead believes in the advice of a well-dressed townsman to go right, because his advice seems more persuasive. However, the townsman is actually a samardocus (con man) so Traveler B never reaches the correct destination.
- The Anecdote of the Adulterer: A man suspends belief that adultery is bad, and commits adultery with another man's wife because it is persuasive to him. Under Academic Skepticism, this man cannot be charged because he acted on what was persuasive to him without assenting belief.
- Conclusion: Suspending belief exposes individuals to an error as defined by the Academic Skeptics.
Skepticism's revival in the sixteenth century
Francisco Sanches's That Nothing is Known (published in 1581 as Quod nihil scitur) is one of the crucial texts of Renaissance skepticism.
Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592)
The most notable figure of the Skepticism revival in the 1500s, Michel de Montaigne wrote about his studies of Academic Skepticism and Pyrrhonism through his Essais.
His most notable writings on skepticism occurred in an essay written mostly in 1575–1576, "Apologie de Raimond Sebond", when he was reading Sextus Empiricus and trying to translate Raimond Sebond's writing, including his proof of Christianity's natural existence. The reception to Montaigne's translations included some criticisms of Sebond's proof. Montaigne responded to some of them in Apologie, including a defense for Sebond's logic that is skeptical in nature and similar to Pyrrhonism. His refutation is as follows:
- Critics claiming Sebond's arguments are weak show how egoistic humans believe that their logic is superior to others'.
- Many animals can be observed to be superior to humans in certain respects. To argue this point, Montaigne even writes about dogs who are logical and creates their own syllogisms to understand the world around them. This was an example used in Sextus Empiricus.
- Since animals also have rationality, the over-glorification of man's mental capabilities is a trap—man's folly. One man's reason cannot be assuredly better than another's as a result.
- Ignorance is even recommended by religion so that an individual can reach faith through obediently following divine instructions to learn, not by one's logic.
Marin Mersenne (1588–1648)
Marin Mersenne was an author, mathematician, scientist, and philosopher. He wrote in defense of science and Christianity against atheists and Pyrrhonists before retiring to encourage development of science and the "new philosophy", which includes philosophers like Gassendi, Descartes, Galileo, and Hobbes. A major work of his in relation to Skepticism is La Verité des Sciences, in which he argues that although we may not be able to know the true nature of things, we can still formulate certain laws and rules for sense-perceptions through science.
Additionally, he points out that we do not doubt everything because:
- Humans do agree about some things, for example, an ant is smaller than an elephant
- There are natural laws governing our sense-perceptions, such as optics, which allow us to eliminate inaccuracies
- Man created tools such as rulers and scales to measure things and eliminate doubts such as bent oars, pigeons' necks, and round towers.
A Pyrrhonist might refute these points by saying that senses deceive, and thus knowledge turns into infinite regress or circular logic. Thus Mersenne argues that this cannot be the case, since commonly agreed upon rules of thumb can be hypothesized and tested over time to ensure that they continue to hold.
Furthermore, if everything can be doubted, the doubt can also be doubted, so on and so forth. Thus, according to Mersenne, something has to be true. Finally, Mersenne writes about all the mathematical, physical, and other scientific knowledge that is true by repeated testing, and has practical use value. Notably, Mersenne was one of the few philosophers who accepted Hobbes' radical ideology—he saw it as a new science of man.
Skepticism in the seventeenth century
Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679)
During his long stay in Paris, Thomas Hobbes was actively involved in the circle of major skeptics like Gassendi and Mersenne who focus on the study of skepticism and epistemology. Unlike his fellow skeptic friends, Hobbes never treated skepticism as a main topic for discussion in his works. Nonetheless, Hobbes was still labeled as a religious skeptic by his contemporaries for raising doubts about Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuch and his political and psychological explanation of the religions. Although Hobbes himself did not go further to challenge other religious principles, his suspicion for the Mosaic authorship did significant damage to the religious traditions and paved the way for later religious skeptics like Spinoza and Isaac La Peyrère to further question some of the fundamental beliefs of the Judeo-Christian religious system. Hobbes' answer to skepticism and epistemology was innovatively political: he believed that moral knowledge and religious knowledge were in their nature relative, and there was no absolute standard of truth governing them. As a result, it was out of political reasons that certain truth standards about religions and ethics were devised and established in order to form a functioning government and stable society.
Baruch Spinoza and religious skepticism
Baruch Spinoza was among the first European philosophers who were religious skeptics. He was quite familiar with the philosophy of Descartes and unprecedentedly extended the application of the Cartesian method to the religious context by analyzing religious texts with it. Spinoza sought to dispute the knowledge-claims of the Judeo-Christian-Islamic religious system by examining its two foundations: the Scripture and the Miracles. He claimed that all Cartesian knowledge, or the rational knowledge should be accessible to the entire population. Therefore, the Scriptures, aside from those by Jesus, should not be considered the secret knowledge attained from God but just the imagination of the prophets. The Scriptures, as a result of this claim, could not serve as a base for knowledge and were reduced to simple ancient historical texts. Moreover, Spinoza also rejected the possibility for the Miracles by simply asserting that people only considered them miraculous due to their lack of understanding of the nature. By rejecting the validity of the Scriptures and the Miracles, Spinoza demolished the foundation for religious knowledge-claim and established his understanding of the Cartesian knowledge as the sole authority of knowledge-claims. Despite being deeply skeptical of the religions, Spinoza was in fact exceedingly anti-skeptical towards reason and rationality. He steadfastly confirmed the legitimacy of reason by associating it with the acknowledgement of God, and thereby skepticism with the rational approach to knowledge was not due to problems with the rational knowledge but from the fundamental lack of understanding of God. Spinoza's religious skepticism and anti-skepticism with reason thus helped him transform epistemology by separating the theological knowledge-claims and the rational knowledge-claims.
Pierre Bayle (1647–1706)
Pierre Bayle was a French philosopher in the late 17th century that was described by Richard Popkin to be a "supersceptic" who carried out the sceptic tradition to the extreme. Bayle was born in a Calvinist family in Carla-Bayle, and during the early stage of his life, he converted into Catholicism before returning to Calvinism. This conversion between religions caused him to leave France for the more religiously tolerant Holland where he stayed and worked for the rest of his life.
Bayle believed that truth cannot be obtained through reason and that all human endeavor to acquire absolute knowledge would inevitably lead to failure. Bayle's main approach was highly skeptical and destructive: he sought to examine and analyze all existing theories in all fields of human knowledge in order to show the faults in their reasoning and thus the absurdity of the theories themselves. In his magnum opus, Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (Historical and Critical Dictionary), Bayle painstakingly identified the logical flaws in several works throughout the history in order to emphasize the absolute futility of rationality. Bayle's complete nullification of reason led him to conclude that faith is the final and only way to truth.
Bayle's real intention behind his extremely destructive works remained controversial. Some described him to be a Fideist, while others speculated him to be a secret Atheist. However, no matter what his original intention was, Bayle did cast significant influence on the upcoming Age of Enlightenment with his destruction of some of the most essential theological ideas and his justification of religious tolerance Atheism in his works.
Skepticism in the Age of Enlightenment
David Hume (1711–1776)
David Hume was among the most influential proponents of philosophical skepticism during the Age of Enlightenment and one of the most notable voices of the Scottish Enlightenment and British Empiricism. He especially espoused skepticism regarding inductive reasoning, and questioned what the foundation of morality was, creating the is–ought problem. His approach to skepticism is considered even more radical than that of Descartes.
Hume argued that any coherent idea must be either a mental copy of an impression (a direct sensory perception) or copies of multiple impressions innovatively combined. Since certain human activities like religion, superstition, and metaphysics are not premised on any actual sense-impressions, their claims to knowledge are logically unjustified. Furthermore, Hume even demonstrates that science is merely a psychological phenomenon based on the association of ideas: often, specifically, an assumption of cause-and-effect relationships that is itself not grounded in any sense-impressions. Thus, even scientific knowledge is logically unjustified, being not actually objective or provable but, rather, mere conjecture flimsily based on our minds perceiving regular correlations between distinct events. Hume thus falls into extreme skepticism regarding the possibility of any certain knowledge. Ultimately, he offers that, at best, a science of human nature is the "only solid foundation for the other sciences".
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)
This article may need to be rewritten to comply with Misplaced Pages's quality standards. You can help. The talk page may contain suggestions. (August 2020) |
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) tried to provide a ground for empirical science against David Hume's skeptical treatment of the notion of cause and effect. Hume (1711–1776) argued that for the notion of cause and effect no analysis is possible which is also acceptable to the empiricist program primarily outlined by John Locke (1632–1704). But, Kant's attempt to give a ground to knowledge in the empirical sciences at the same time cut off the possibility of knowledge of any other knowledge, especially what Kant called "metaphysical knowledge". So, for Kant, empirical science was legitimate, but metaphysics and philosophy was mostly illegitimate. The most important exception to this demarcation of the legitimate from the illegitimate was ethics, the principles of which Kant argued can be known by pure reason without appeal to the principles required for empirical knowledge. Thus, with respect to metaphysics and philosophy in general (ethics being the exception), Kant was a skeptic. This skepticism as well as the explicit skepticism of G. E. Schulze gave rise to a robust discussion of skepticism in German idealistic philosophy, especially by Hegel. Kant's idea was that the real world (the noumenon or thing-in-itself) was inaccessible to human reason (though the empirical world of nature can be known to human understanding) and therefore we can never know anything about the ultimate reality of the world. Hegel argued against Kant that although Kant was right that using what Hegel called "finite" concepts of "the understanding" precluded knowledge of reality, we were not constrained to use only "finite" concepts and could actually acquire knowledge of reality using "infinite concepts" that arise from self-consciousness.
Skepticism in the 20th century and contemporary philosophy
G. E. Moore famously presented the "Here is one hand" argument against skepticism in his 1925 paper, "A Defence of Common Sense". Moore claimed that he could prove that the external world exists by simply presenting the following argument while holding up his hands: "Here is one hand; here is another hand; therefore, there are at least two objects; therefore, external-world skepticism fails". His argument was developed for the purpose of vindicating common sense and refuting skepticism. Ludwig Wittgenstein later argued in his On Certainty (posthumously published in 1969) that Moore's argument rested on the way that ordinary language is used, rather than on anything about knowledge.
In contemporary philosophy, Richard Popkin was a particularly influential scholar on the topic of skepticism. His account of the history of skepticism given in The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle (first edition published as The History of Scepticism From Erasmus to Descartes) was accepted as the standard for contemporary scholarship in the area for decades after its release in 1960. Barry Stroud also published a number of works on philosophical skepticism, most notably his 1984 monograph, The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. From the mid-1990s, Stroud, alongside Richard Fumerton, put forward influential anti-externalist arguments in favour of a position called "metaepistemological scepticism". Other contemporary philosophers known for their work on skepticism include James Pryor, Keith DeRose, and Peter Klein.
History of skepticism in non-Western philosophy
Ancient Indian skepticism
Ajñana
Main article: AjñanaAjñana (literally 'non-knowledge') were the skeptical school of ancient Indian philosophy. It was a śramaṇa movement and a major rival of early Buddhism and Jainism. They have been recorded in Buddhist and Jain texts. They held that it was impossible to obtain knowledge of metaphysical nature or ascertain the truth value of philosophical propositions; and even if knowledge was possible, it was useless and disadvantageous for final salvation.
Buddhism
Main article: Buddhist philosophyThe historical Buddha asserted certain doctrines as true, such as the possibility of nirvana; however, he also upheld a form of skepticism with regards to certain questions which he left "un-expounded" (avyākata) and some he saw as "incomprehensible" (acinteyya). Because the Buddha saw these questions (which tend to be of metaphysical topics) as unhelpful on the path and merely leading to confusion and "a thicket of views", he promoted suspension of judgment towards them. This allowed him to carve out an epistemic middle way between what he saw as the extremes of claiming absolute objectivity (associated with the claims to omniscience of the Jain Mahavira) and extreme skepticism (associated with the Ajñana thinker Sanjaya Belatthiputta).
Later Buddhist philosophy remained highly skeptical of Indian metaphysical arguments. The Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna in particular has been seen as the founder of the Madhyamaka school, which has been in turn compared with Greek Skepticism. Nagarjuna's statement that he has "no thesis" (pratijña) has parallels in the statements of Sextus Empiricus of having "no position". Nagarjuna famously opens his magnum opus, the Mulamadhyamakakarika, with the statement that the Buddha claimed that true happiness was found through dispelling 'vain thinking' (prapañca, also "conceptual proliferation").
According to Richard P. Hayes, the Buddhist philosopher Dignaga is also a kind of skeptic, which is in line with most early Buddhist philosophy. Hayes writes:
...in both early Buddhism and in the Skeptics one can find the view put forward that man's pursuit of happiness, the highest good, is obstructed by his tenacity in holding ungrounded and unnecessary opinions about all manner of things. Much of Buddhist philosophy, I shall argue, can be seen as an attempt to break this habit of holding on to opinions.
Scholars like Adrian Kuzminski have argued that Pyrrho of Elis (ca. 365–270) might have been influenced by Indian Buddhists during his journey with Alexander the Great.
Cārvāka philosophy
Main article: CārvākaThe Cārvāka (Sanskrit: चार्वाक) school of materialism, also known as Lokāyata, is a classically cited (but historically disputed) school of ancient Indian philosophy. While no texts or authoritative doctrine have survived, followers of this system are frequently mentioned in philosophical treatises of other schools, often as an initial counterpoint against which to assert their own arguments.
Cārvāka is classified as a "heterodox" (nāstika) system, characterized as a materialistic and atheistic school of thought. This school was also known for being strongly skeptical of the claims of Indian religions, such as reincarnation and karma.
Jainism
Main articles: Anekantavada and SyadvadaWhile Jain philosophy claims that is it possible to achieve omniscience, absolute knowledge (Kevala Jnana), at the moment of enlightenment, their theory of anekāntavāda or 'many sided-ness', also known as the principle of relative pluralism, allows for a practical form of skeptical thought regarding philosophical and religious doctrines (for un-enlightened beings, not all-knowing arihants).
According to this theory, the truth or the reality is perceived differently from different points of view, and that no single point of view is the complete truth. Jain doctrine states that, an object has infinite modes of existence and qualities and, as such, they cannot be completely perceived in all its aspects and manifestations, due to inherent limitations of the humans. Anekāntavāda is literally the doctrine of non-onesidedness or manifoldness; it is often translated as "non-absolutism". Syādvāda is the theory of conditioned predication which provides an expression to anekānta by recommending that epithet "Syād" be attached to every expression. Syādvāda is not only an extension of Anekānta ontology, but a separate system of logic capable of standing on its own force. As reality is complex, no single proposition can express the nature of reality fully. Thus the term "syāt" should be prefixed before each proposition giving it a conditional point of view and thus removing any dogmatism in the statement. For Jains, fully enlightened beings are able to see reality from all sides and thus have ultimate knowledge of all things. This idea of omniscience was criticized by Buddhists such as Dharmakirti.
Ancient Chinese philosophy
Zhuang Zhou (c. 369 – c. 286 BCE)
Zhuang Zhou (莊子,"Master Zhuang") was a famous ancient Chinese Taoism philosopher during the Hundred Schools of Thought period. Zhuang Zhou demonstrated his skeptical thinking through several anecdotes in the preeminent work Zhuangzi attributed to him:
- "The Debate on the Joy of Fish" (知魚之樂) : In this anecdote, Zhuang Zhou argued with his fellow philosopher Hui Shi whether they knew the fish in the pond were happy or not, and Zhuang Zhou made the famous observation that "You are not I. How do you know that I do not know that the fish are happy?" (Autumn Floods 秋水篇, Zhuangzi)
- "The Butterfly of the Dream"(周公夢蝶) : The paradox of "Butterfly Dream" described Zhuang Zhou's confusion after dreaming himself to be a butterfly: "But he didn't know if he was Zhuang Zhou who had dreamt he was a butterfly, or a butterfly dreaming that he was Zhuang Zhou." (Discussion on Making All Things Equal 齊物篇, Zhuangzi)
Through these anecdotes in Zhuangzi, Zhuang Zhou indicated his belief in the limitation of language and human communication and the inaccessibility of universal truth. This establishes him as a skeptic. But he was by no means a radical skeptic: he only applied skeptical methods partially, in arguments demonstrating his Taoist beliefs. He held the Taoist beliefs themselves dogmatically.
Wang Chong (27 – c. 100 CE)
Wang Chong (王充) was the leading figure of the skeptic branch of the Confucianism school in China during the first century CE. He introduced a method of rational critique and applied it to the widespread dogmatism thinking of his age like phenomenology (the main contemporary Confucianism ideology that linked all natural phenomena with human ethics), state-led cults, and popular superstition. His own philosophy incorporated both Taoism and Confucianism thinkings, and it was based on a secular, rational practice of developing hypotheses based on natural events to explain the universe which exemplified a form of naturalism that resembled the philosophical idea of Epicureans like Lucretius.
Medieval Islamic philosophy
The Incoherence of the Philosophers, written by the scholar Al-Ghazali (1058–1111), marks a major turn in Islamic epistemology. His encounter with skepticism led Ghazali to embrace a form of theological occasionalism, or the belief that all causal events and interactions are not the product of material conjunctions but rather the immediate and present will of God.
In the autobiography Ghazali wrote towards the end of his life, The Deliverance From Error (Al-munqidh min al-ḍalāl ), Ghazali recounts how, once a crisis of epistemological skepticism was resolved by "a light which God Most High cast into my breast...the key to most knowledge", he studied and mastered the arguments of Kalam, Islamic philosophy, and Ismailism. Though appreciating what was valid in the first two of these, at least, he determined that all three approaches were inadequate and found ultimate value only in the mystical experience and spiritual insight he attained as a result of following Sufi practices. William James, in Varieties of Religious Experience, considered the autobiography an important document for "the purely literary student who would like to become acquainted with the inwardness of religions other than the Christian", comparing it to recorded personal religious confessions and autobiographical literature in the Christian tradition.
Aztec philosophy
Recordings of Aztec philosophy suggest that the elite classes believed in an essentially panentheistic worldview, in which teotl represents a unified, underlying universal force. Human beings cannot truly perceive teotl due to its chaotic, constantly changing nature, just the "masks"/facets it is manifested as.
See also
- Ajñana
- Anti-realism
- Benson Mates
- Brain in a vat
- Celia Green
- Fallibilism
- David Hume
- Dream argument
- Five minute hypothesis
- Münchhausen trilemma
- Nihilism
- Pierre Bayle
- Problem of the criterion
- Problem of induction
- Pseudoskepticism
- Pyrrho
- Pyrrhonism
- Sextus Empiricus
- Simulated reality
- Solipsism
- Trivialism (opposite of skepticism)
- Underdetermination
- Zhuang Zhou
References
- ^ "Skepticism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved July 12, 2020.
- "Certainty". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved July 12, 2020.
- ^ Popkin, Richard Henry (2003). The history of scepticism: from Savonarola to Bayle. Popkin, Richard Henry (Rev. and expanded ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-535539-0. OCLC 65192690.
- ^ Goldstick, D. (May 1, 1983). "Four Forms of Philosophical Scepticism". University of Toronto Quarterly. 52 (3): 235–240. doi:10.3138/utq.52.3.235. S2CID 170733016.
- ^ Hansson, Sven Ove (September 2017). "The Uses and Misuses of Philosophical Scepticism: Editorial". Theoria. 83 (3): 169–174. doi:10.1111/theo.12123.
- Olsson, Erik J. (2005). "Not Giving the Skeptic a Hearing: "Pragmatism and Radical Doubt"". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 70 (1): 98–126. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00507.x. ISSN 0031-8205. JSTOR 40040781.
- ^ Comesaña, Juan; Klein, Peter (2019). "Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved August 24, 2022.
- ^ DeRose, Keith; Warfield, Ted A. (1999). "1. Introduction: Responding to Skepticism". Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511827-8.
- ^ Popkin, Richard H. "skepticism". www.britannica.com. Retrieved August 23, 2022.
- ^ Stroud, Barry; Stroud, Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry (July 5, 1984). "Preface". The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-824761-6.
- Cohen, Stewart (1996). Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
- ^ Stroud, Barry; Stroud, Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor of Philosophy Emeritus Barry (July 5, 1984). "II Philosophical Scepticism and Everyday Life". The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-824761-6.
- Hinton, J. M. (1989). "Scepticism: Philosophical and Everyday". Philosophy. 64 (248): 219–243. doi:10.1017/S0031819100044491. ISSN 0031-8191. JSTOR 3751409. S2CID 144250265.
- ^ Greco, John (September 2, 2009). "Introduction". The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism (1 ed.). Oxford University Press. pp. 3–7. ISBN 978-0-19-518321-4.
- ^ Le Morvan, Pierre (2011). "Healthy Skepticism and Practical Wisdom". Logos & Episteme. 2 (1): 87–102. doi:10.5840/logos-episteme20112151.
- Merton, R. K. (1942). "The Normative Structure of Science". in Merton, Robert King (1973). The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-52091-9.
- Vogt, Katja (2021). "Ancient Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved August 30, 2022.
- Reed, Baron (December 11, 2018). Skepticism as a Way of Life. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-39353-0.
- Williams, Michael (2001). "Chapter 5: Agrippa's Trilemma". Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology. Oxford University Press. p. 61. ISBN 978-0-19-289256-0.
- ^ "SKEPTICISM". Encyclopedia of Empiricism. 1997.
- ^ Bailey, Alan (1990). "Pyrrhonean Scepticism and the Self-Refutation Argument". The Philosophical Quarterly. 40 (158): 27–44. doi:10.2307/2219965. ISSN 0031-8094. JSTOR 2219965.
- Kreeft p. 373
- Baldwin, Tom (2010). "George Edward Moore: 6. Common Sense and Certainty". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved September 1, 2022.
- Schulte, Günter (2007). "Gehirnfunktion Und Willensfreiheit. Schopenhauers Neurophilosophische Wende". Schopenhauer Jahrbuch. 88: 51–70.
- Vogt, Katja (2019). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield : Acumen. pp. 108–109. ISBN 978-1-84465-409-3. OCLC 715184861.
Undecidability and the ten modes As part of his Pyrrhonian revival Aenesidemus assembled various kinds of skeptical arguments, or modes, designed to induce epoche.
- Diogenes Laërtius 9:80–88
- Eusebius. "Praeparatio Evangelica Book XIV". Tertullian Project. Retrieved January 27, 2023.
- Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield : Acumen. pp. 120–121. ISBN 978-1-84465-409-3. OCLC 715184861.
Pyrrhonism, in whatever form it might have taken after Timon's death in 230 BCE, was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention
- ^ Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield : Acumen. pp. 102–103. ISBN 978-1-84465-409-3. OCLC 715184861.
Aenesidemus criticized his fellow Academics for being dogmatic...Aenesidemus committed his scepticism to writing probably some time in the early-to-mid first century BCE...leading Aenesidemus to dismiss them as "Stoics fighting against Stoics."
- Sextus, Empiricus (1990). Outlines of pyrrhonism. Robert Gregg Bury. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. ISBN 0-87975-597-0. OCLC 23367477.
Those who believe they have discovered it are the "dogmatists", specially so called - Aristotle, for example, and Epicurus and the Stoics and certain others; Cleitomachus and Carneades and other Academics treat it as inapprehensible:the skeptics keep on searching. Hence it seems reasonable to hold the main types of philosophy are three - the dogmatic, the Academic, and the skeptic.
- Plutarch, Sulla 12; cf. Appian, Roman History xii, 5.30 Archived September 12, 2015, at the Wayback Machine
- On the ten modes, see Sextus Empiricus. Outlines of Skepticism I.35–164.
- Brochard, V., The Greek Skeptics.
- ^ Dutton, Blake D. (2016). Augustine and academic skepticism: a philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-1-5017-0355-3. OCLC 951625897.
- Hick, John (1970). Classical and contemporary readings in the philosophy of religion (2nd ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-135269-8. OCLC 90682.
- Francisco Sanchez, That Nothing is Known, Cambridge University Press, 1989.
- Clarke, Desmond M. (2016). French philosophy, 1572–1675. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-874957-8. OCLC 923850410.
- ^ Maia Neto, José Raimundo; Paganini, Gianni; Laursen, John Christian, eds. (2009). Skepticism in the modern age: building on the work of Richard Popkin. Leiden: Brill. ISBN 978-90-474-3190-9. OCLC 700517388.
- Nadler, Steven M., ed. (2002). A companion to early modern philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell Pub. ISBN 978-0-631-21800-5. OCLC 49394201.
- Chappell, Vere Claiborne, ed. (1992). Grotius to Gassendi. New York: Garland Pub. ISBN 978-0-8153-0576-7. OCLC 24846343.
- Missner, Marshall (1983). "Skepticism and Hobbes's Political Philosophy". Journal of the History of Ideas. 44 (3): 407–427. doi:10.2307/2709174. JSTOR 2709174.
- Black, Sam (1997). "Science and Moral Skepticism in Hobbes". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 27 (2): 173–207. doi:10.1080/00455091.1997.10717477. JSTOR 40231980. S2CID 170567466.
- Laursen, John Christian; Paganini, Gianni, eds. (2015). Skepticism and political thought in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-1-4426-4921-7. OCLC 904548214.
- Batnitzky, Leora (December 2003). "Spinoza's Critique of Religious Authority: Spinoza's Critique of Miracles". Cardozo Law Review. 25: 57.
- ^ Matytsin, Anton M. (2016). The specter of skepticism in the age of Enlightenment. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-1-4214-2052-3. OCLC 960048885.
- ^ Lennon, Thomas M. (2002). "What Kind of a Skeptic Was Bayle?". Midwest Studies in Philosophy. 26–1: 258–279. doi:10.1111/1475-4975.261066.
- Morris, William Edward, and Charlotte R. Brown. 2019 . "David Hume Archived May 3, 1998, at the Wayback Machine." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab. Retrieved 10 August 2020.
- Cranston, Maurice, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 2020 "David Hume Archived June 21, 2015, at the Wayback Machine." Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 10 August 2020.
- Hume, David. 1739. A Treatise of Human Nature 1. London: John Noon. Retrieved 19 May 2020. p. 7.
- David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739), Book I, "Of the Understanding" and David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748).
- See G. E. Schulze, Aenesidemus (1792), excerpted in Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 2000. See also Frederick C. Beiser, The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1987; Chapter 9, "Schulze's Skepticism".
- See (1) H. S. Harris, "Skepticism, Dogmatism and Speculation in the Critical Journal" (1985), in Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 2000; (2) G. W. F. Hegel, "On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy, Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One", Translated by H. S. Harris, in di Giovanni and Harris (2000) (cited just above); and (3) Michael N. Forster, Hegel and Skepticism, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1989.
- Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, The Encyclopedia Logic (1830), § 28, pp. 65–68, Translated by T. F. Garaets, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing, 1991.
- Jesús Padilla Gálvez, Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative, in: Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition, António Marques & Rui Bertrand Romao (Eds.), Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Wien: Peter Lang, 2020, pp. 113–122. ISBN 978-3-0343-1595-1.
- Sedley, David Louis (2005). Sublimity and skepticism in Montaigne and Milton. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. ISBN 978-0-472-11528-0. OCLC 60715259.
- Stroud, Barry (1984). "The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism". Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198247613.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-824761-6. Retrieved August 11, 2020.
- Pritchard, Duncan; Ranalli, Chris (2016). "On Metaepistemological Scepticism". In Bergmann, Michael; Coppenger, Brett (eds.). Intellectual Assurance: Essays on Traditional Epistemic Internalism. Oxford University Press.
- Kalupahana, David J. A History of Buddhist Philosophy: Continuities and Discontinuities, page 21.
- The Cowherds. Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2011, pp. 115–116.
- Hayes, Richard P. Dignāga on the interpretation of signs, page 53.
- Hayes, Richard P. Dignāga on the interpretation of signs, page 35.
- Kuzminski, Adrian. Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism (Studies in Comparative Philosophy and Religion), 2008.
- Dundas, Paul (2002). The Jains. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-26606-2.
- ^ Koller, John M. (July 2000). "Syādvāda as the epistemological key to the Jaina middle way metaphysics of Anekāntavāda". Philosophy East and West. 50 (3): 400–407. ISSN 0031-8221. JSTOR 1400182. ProQuest 216882163.
- Chatterjea, Tara (2001). Knowledge and Freedom in Indian Philosophy. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. pp. 77–87. ISBN 978-0-7391-0692-1.
- ^ Zhuangzi (2017) . The Complete works of Zhuangzi. Translated by Watson, Burton. New York: Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-16474-0. OCLC 826640070.
- Berthel, Ken (December 1, 2015). "Language in Zhuangzi: A Theme that Reveals the Nature of its Relativism and Skepticism". Journal of Chinese Philosophy. 42: 562–576. doi:10.1111/1540-6253.12215. ISSN 1540-6253.
- Xuerong, Ouyang (December 2003). "略论王充的怀疑主义". Journal of Kaifeng University. 17–04: 11–13.
- Needham, Joseph (1978). The shorter Science and civilisation in China: an abridgement of Joseph Needham's original text. Ronan, Colin A. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-23582-2. OCLC 3345021.
- Annotated translations by Richard Joseph McCarthy (Freedom and Fulfillment, Boston: Twayne, 1980; Deliverance From Error, Louisville, Ky.: Fons Vitae, 1999) and George F. McLean (Deliverance from error and mystical union with the Almighty, Washington, D.C.: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy, 2001). An earlier translation by William Montgomery Watt was first published in 1953 (The faith and practice of al-Ghazālī, London: G. Allen and Unwin).
- McCarthy 1980, p. 66
- William James, Varieties of Religious Experience, Harvard University Press, 1985, p. 319 .
- James Maffie (2005). "Aztec Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- James Maffie (2014). Aztec Philosophy: Understanding a World in Motion. University Press of Colorado
Further reading
- Popkin, Richard H. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Popkin, Richard H. and J. R. Maia Neto, eds. 2007. Skepticism: An Anthology. New York: Prometheus Books.
- Beiser, Frederick C. 1987. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Breker, Christian. 2011. Einführender Kommentar zu Sextus Empiricus' "Grundriss der pyrrhonischen Skepsis", Mainz, 2011: electr. publication, University of Mainz. available online (comment on Sextus Empiricus' "Outlines of Pyrrhonism" in German language)
- di Giovanni, George and H. S. Harris, eds. 2000. Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism. Translated with Introductions by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.
- Forster, Michael N. 1989. Hegel and Skepticism. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
- Harris, H. S. 1985. "Skepticism, Dogmatism and Speculation in the Critical Journal". In di Giovanni and Harris 2000.
- Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel. 1802. "On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy, Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One". Translated by H. S. Harris. In di Giovanni and Harris 2000.
- Leavitt, Fred. 2021. "If Ignorance is Bliss We Should All be Ecstatic." Open Books.
- Lehrer, Keith, 1971. "Why Not Scepticism?" Philosophical Forum, vol. II, pp. 283-298.
- Jesús Padilla Gálvez, Scepticism as Philosophical Superlative, in: Wittgenstein and the Sceptical Tradition, António Marques & Rui Bertrand Romao (Eds.), Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Wien: Peter Lang, 2020, pp. 113–122.
- François-Xavier de Peretti, « Stop Doubting with Descartes », dans M. Garcia-Valdecasas, J. Milburn, J.-B. Guillon (éds.), « Anti-skepticism », Topoi. An International Review of Philosophy, Springer Nature, on line 3.11.2022
- François-Xavier de Peretti, « Descartes sceptique malgré lui ? », International Journal for the Study of Skepticism, 11 (3), 2021, Brill, Leyde, pp. 177-192. Online publication date: 15 octobre 2020. Doi:https://doi.org/10.1163/22105700-bja10016
- Thorsrud, Harald. 2009. Ancient Scepticism. Berkeley: University of California Press.
- Unger, Peter. 1975. Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. 2002.
- Zeller, Eduard and Oswald J. Reichel. 1892. The Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.
External links
- Klein, Peter. "Skepticism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Ancient Greek Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Renaissance Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Contemporary Skepticism entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Responses to skepticism by Keith DeRose
- Article: Skepticism and Denial by Stephen Novella MD, The New England Journal of Skepticism
- Classical Skepticism by Peter Suber
- Review and summary of Skepticism and the Veil of Perception by Michael Huemer
- Sullivan, Margaret (December 5, 2019). "Wall-to-wall impeachment coverage is not changing any minds. Here's how journalists can reach the undecided". The Washington Post.
Columnist Michelle Goldberg of the New York Times offered a name Wednesday for one aspect of what's happening before our eyes. Responding to the absurd statement of Rep. Douglas A. Collins (R-Ga.) — "there are no set facts here" — she said it summed up the long-term Republican strategy: "epistemological nihilism."
Skepticism | |
---|---|
Types of skepticism | |
Skeptical philosophies | |
Skeptical philosophers | |
Skeptical scenarios | |
Responses | |
Lists |