Misplaced Pages

Doubling the cube: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 19:19, 21 December 2006 editWill Beback (talk | contribs)112,162 edits rm LaRouche sources← Previous edit Latest revision as of 20:27, 18 December 2024 edit undoDavid Eppstein (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Administrators226,722 edits templatize some refs 
(308 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Ancient geometric construction problem}}
'''Doubling the cube''' is one of the three most famous ] problems unsolvable by ] construction. It was known to the ], and earlier to the ].
{2}</math> = 1.2599210498948732... {{OEIS2C|A002580}}).]]


'''Doubling the cube''', also known as the '''Delian problem''', is an ancient{{efn|The Delian problem shows up in Plato's '']'' ({{circa|380 BC}}) VII.530}}<ref name="Kern1934">{{Cite book|last1=Kern|first1=Willis F.|title=Solid Mensuration With Proofs|last2=Bland|first2=James R.|publisher=John Wiley & Sons|year=1934|location=New York|language=en}}</ref>{{Rp|page=9}} ] problem. Given the ] of a ], the problem requires the construction of the edge of a second cube whose ] is double that of the first. As with the related problems of ] and ], doubling the cube is now known to be impossible to construct by using only a ], but even in ancient times solutions were known that employed other methods.
To ''double the cube'' means to be given a ] of some side length ''s'' and volume ''V'', and to construct a new cube, larger than the first, with volume 2''V'' and therefore side length <math>s\cdot\sqrt{2}</math>. The problem is known to be impossible to solve with only compass and straightedge, because <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is not a ].

According to Eutocius, Archytas was the first to solve the problem of doubling the cube (the so-called Delian problem) with an ingenious geometric construction.<ref>{{cite book
| last = Menn | first = Stephen
| editor1-last = Holmes | editor1-first = Brooke
| editor2-last = Fischer | editor2-first = Klaus-Dietrich
| contribution = How Archytas doubled the cube
| doi = 10.1515/9783110336337-021
| pages = 407–436
| publisher = De Gruyter
| series = Beiträge zur Altertumskunde
| title = The Frontiers of Ancient Science: Essays in honor of Heinrich von Staden
| volume = 338
| year = 2015}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal
| last = Masià | first = Ramon
| doi = 10.1007/s00407-015-0165-9
| issue = 2
| journal = Archive for History of Exact Sciences
| mr = 3458183
| pages = 175–204
| title = A new reading of Archytas' doubling of the cube and its implications
| volume = 70
| year = 2016}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal
| last = Guilbeau | first = Lucye
| doi = 10.2307/3027812
| issue = 4
| journal = Mathematics News Letter
| jstor = 3027812
| pages = 8–12
| title = The history of the solution of the cubic equation
| volume = 5
| year = 1930}}</ref> The nonexistence of a compass-and-straightedge solution was finally proven by ] in 1837.

In algebraic terms, doubling a ] requires the construction of a ] of length {{math|''x''}}, where {{math|1=''x''<sup>3</sup> = 2}}; in other words, {{math|''x'' {{=}} <math>\sqrt{2}</math>}}, the '''cube root of two'''. This is because a cube of side length 1 has a volume of {{nowrap|1=1<sup>3</sup> = 1}}, and a cube of twice that volume (a volume of 2) has a side length of the ] of 2. The impossibility of doubling the cube is therefore ] to the statement that <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is not a ]. This is a consequence of the fact that the coordinates of a new point constructed by a compass and straightedge are roots of ]s over the field generated by the coordinates of previous points, of no greater ] than a ]. This implies that the ] of the ] generated by a constructible point must be a power of 2. The field extension generated by <math>\sqrt{2}</math>, however, is of degree 3.

==Proof of impossibility==
We begin with the unit line segment defined by ] (0,0) and (1,0) in the ]. We are required to construct a line segment defined by two points separated by a distance of <math>\sqrt{2}</math>. It is easily shown that compass and straightedge constructions would allow such a line segment to be freely moved to touch the ], ] with the unit line segment - so equivalently we may consider the task of constructing a line segment from (0,0) to (<math>\sqrt{2}</math>, 0), which entails constructing the point (<math>\sqrt{2}</math>, 0).

Respectively, the tools of a compass and straightedge allow us to create ] ] on one previously defined point and passing through another, and to create lines passing through two previously defined points. Any newly defined point either arises as the result of the ] of two such circles, as the intersection of a circle and a line, or as the intersection of two lines. An exercise of elementary ] shows that in all three cases, both the {{mvar|x}}- and {{mvar|y}}-coordinates of the newly defined point satisfy a polynomial of degree no higher than a quadratic, with ] that are additions, subtractions, multiplications, and divisions involving the coordinates of the previously defined points (and rational numbers). Restated in more abstract terminology, the new {{mvar|x}}- and {{mvar|y}}-coordinates have ]s of degree at most 2 over the ] of {{math|]}} generated by the previous coordinates. Therefore, the ] of the ] corresponding to each new coordinate is 2 or 1.

So, given a coordinate of any constructed point, we may proceed ] backwards through the {{mvar|x}}- and {{mvar|y}}-coordinates of the points in the order that they were defined until we reach the original pair of points (0,0) and (1,0). As every field extension has degree 2 or 1, and as the field extension over ] of the coordinates of the original pair of points is clearly of degree 1, it follows from the ] that the degree of the field extension over <math>\mathbb{Q}</math> of any coordinate of a constructed point is a ].

Now, {{math|1=''p''(''x'') = ''x''<sup>3</sup> − 2 = 0}} is easily seen to be ] over ] – any ] would involve a ] {{math|(''x'' − ''k'')}} for some {{math|''k'' ∈ <math>\mathbb{Z}</math>}}, and so {{math|''k''}} must be a ] of {{math|''p''(''x'')}}; but also {{math|''k''}} must divide 2 (by the ]); that is, {{math|1=''k'' = 1, 2, −1}} or {{math|−2}}, and none of these are roots of {{math|''p''(''x'')}}. By ], {{math|''p''(''x'')}} is also irreducible over <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>, and is thus a minimal polynomial over <math>\mathbb{Q}</math> for <math>\sqrt{2}</math>. The field extension <math>\mathbb{Q} (\sqrt{2}):\mathbb{Q}</math> is therefore of degree 3. But this is not a power of 2, so by the above:
*<math>\sqrt{2}</math> is not the coordinate of a constructible point, so
*a line segment of <math>\sqrt{2}</math> cannot be constructed with ruler and compass, and
*the cube cannot be doubled using only a ruler and a compass.


==History== ==History==
The problem owes its name to a story concerning the citizens of ], who consulted the oracle at ] in order to learn how to defeat a plague sent by ].<ref name="Zhmud">{{Cite book |last=Zhmudʹ |first=Leonid I︠A︡kovlevich |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oX28qf7LKdoC&pg=PA84 |title=The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity |date=2006 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-017966-8 |pages=84, quoting Plutarch and Theon of Smyrna |language=en}}</ref>{{r|Kern1934|p=9}} According to ],<ref>{{Cite web |title=Plutarch, De E apud Delphos, section 6 386.4 |url=https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus:text:2008.01.0243:section=6 |access-date=2024-09-17 |website=www.perseus.tufts.edu}}</ref> however, the citizens of ] consulted the ] at ] to find a solution for their internal political problems at the time, which had intensified relationships among the citizens. The oracle responded that they must double the size of the altar to Apollo, which was a regular cube. The answer seemed strange to the Delians, and they consulted ], who was able to interpret the oracle as the mathematical problem of doubling the volume of a given cube, thus explaining the oracle as the advice of Apollo for the citizens of ] to occupy themselves with the study of geometry and mathematics in order to calm down their passions.<ref>], De genio Socratis 579.B</ref>
According to legend, the citizens of ] consulted the ] of ] at ] in 430&nbsp;BC, in order to learn how to defeat a ] which was ravaging their lands. The oracle responded that to stop the plague, they must double the size of their altar. The Athenians dutifully doubled each side of the altar, and the plague increased. The correct interpretation was that they must double the ''volume'' of their altar, not merely its side length; this proved to be a most difficult problem indeed, but was solved in 350 BC to the efforts of ]. The only problem was that the plague was finished several decades age .It is due to this legend that the problem is often known as the '''Delian problem'''.


According to ], Plato gave the problem to ] and ] and ], who solved the problem using mechanical means, earning a rebuke from Plato for not solving the problem using ].<ref>(Plut., ''Quaestiones convivales'' , 718ef)</ref> This may be why the problem is referred to in the 350s BC by the author of the pseudo-Platonic '']'' (388e) as still unsolved.<ref>Carl Werner Müller, ''Die Kurzdialoge der Appendix Platonica'', Munich: Wilhelm Fink, 1975, pp. 105–106</ref> However another version of the story (attributed to ] by ]) says that all three found solutions but they were too abstract to be of practical value.<ref>{{citation|title=The Ancient Tradition of Geometric Problems|title-link= The Ancient Tradition of Geometric Problems |series=Dover Books on Mathematics|first=Wilbur Richard|last=Knorr|author-link=Wilbur Knorr|publisher=Courier Dover Publications|year=1986|isbn=9780486675329|at=}}.</ref>
False claims of doubling the cube with compass and straightedge abound in mathematical ] literature (]).


A significant development in finding a solution to the problem was the discovery by ] that it is equivalent to finding two ] proportionals between a line segment and another with twice the length.<ref name="Heath">T.L. Heath '']'', Vol. 1</ref> In modern notation, this means that given segments of lengths {{math|''a''}} and {{math|2''a''}}, the duplication of the cube is equivalent to finding segments of lengths {{math|''r''}} and {{math|''s''}} so that
Although Menaechmus solved this problem, doubling the cube was impossible in the plane with the compass and straightedge, ancient Greek mathematician ] did solve this problem in 4th century B.C. using geometric construction in three dimensions, determining a certain point as the intersection of three surfaces of revolution....
:<math>\frac{a}{r} = \frac{r}{s} = \frac{s}{2a} .</math>


In turn, this means that
==Solutions==
:<math>r=a\cdot\sqrt{2}.</math>
]
But ] proved in 1837 that the ] of 2 is not ]; that is, it cannot be constructed with ].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Lützen |first=Jesper |date=24 January 2010 |title=The Algebra of Geometric Impossibility: Descartes and Montucla on the Impossibility of the Duplication of the Cube and the Trisection of the Angle |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1600-0498.2009.00160.x |journal=Centaurus |language=en |volume=52 |issue=1 |pages=4–37 |doi=10.1111/j.1600-0498.2009.00160.x}}</ref>
There are many ways to construct <math>\sqrt{2}</math> which involve tools other than compass and straightedge. In fact, some of these tools can themselves be constructed using compass and straightedge, but must be cut out of a sheet of paper before they can be used. For example, construct a ruler with a single unit distance marked on it. Construct an equilateral triangle ABC with side length 1, and extend side <math>\overline{AB}</math> by one unit to form the line segment <math>\overline{ABD}</math>. Extend side <math>\overline{BC}</math> to form the ray <math>\overrightarrow{BCE}</math>, and draw the ray <math>\overrightarrow{DCF}</math>. Now take the ruler and place it such that it passes through vertex A and intersects <math>\overline{DCF}</math> at G and <math>\overline{BCE}</math> at H, such that the distance GH is exactly 1. The distance AG will then be precisely <math>\sqrt{2}</math>.


==Solutions via means other than compass and straightedge==
Other more complicated methods of doubling the cube involve the ] or the ].
Menaechmus' original solution involves the intersection of two ] curves. Other more complicated methods of doubling the cube involve ], the ], the ], or the ]. ], a probably female mathematician of ancient Greece, found a numerically accurate approximate solution using planes in three dimensions, but was heavily criticized by ] for not providing a proper ].<ref>{{cite book|last=Knorr|first=Wilbur Richard|author-link=Wilbur Knorr|contribution=Pappus' texts on cube duplication|doi=10.1007/978-1-4612-3690-0_5|pages=|publisher=Birkhäuser|location=Boston|title=Textual Studies in Ancient and Medieval Geometry|url=https://archive.org/details/textualstudiesin0000knor|url-access=registration|year=1989|isbn=9780817633875 }}</ref> ] solved the problem in the 4th century BC using geometric construction in three dimensions, determining a certain point as the intersection of three surfaces of revolution.


Descartes theory of geometric solution of equations uses a parabola to introduce cubic equations, in this way it is possible to set up an equation whose solution is a cube root of two. Note that the parabola itself is not constructible except by three dimensional methods.
==External link==
* at ]


False claims of doubling the cube with compass and straightedge abound in mathematical ] literature (]).


Origami may also be used to construct the ].
]


===Using a marked ruler===
]
]
]
There is a simple ] using a marked ruler for a length which is the cube root of 2 times another length.<ref>{{cite book |title=100 Great Problems of Elementary Mathematics |first=Heinrich |last=Dörrie |publisher=Dover |year=1965 |page=171 |isbn=0486-61348-8}}</ref>
]

]
#Mark a ruler with the given length; this will eventually be GH.
]
#Construct an equilateral triangle ABC with the given length as side.
]
#Extend AB an equal amount again to D.
]
#Extend the line BC forming the line CE.
]
#Extend the line DC forming the line CF.
#Place the marked ruler so it goes through A and one end, G, of the marked length falls on ray CF and the other end of the marked length, H, falls on ray CE. Thus GH is the given length.

Then AG is the given length times <math>\sqrt{2}</math>.

==In music theory==
In ], a natural analogue of doubling is the ] (a musical interval caused by doubling the frequency of a tone), and a natural analogue of a cube is dividing the octave into three parts, each the same ]. In this sense, the problem of doubling the cube is solved by the ] in ]. This is a musical interval that is exactly one third of an octave. It multiplies the frequency of a tone by <math>2^{4/12}=2^{1/3}=\sqrt{2}</math>, the side length of the Delian cube.<ref>{{citation|first=R. C.|last=Phillips|title=The equal tempered scale|journal=Musical Opinion and Music Trade Review|volume=29|issue=337|date=October 1905|pages=41–42|id={{ProQuest|7191936}}}}</ref>

== Explanatory notes ==
{{Notelist}}

==References==
{{Reflist}}

== External links ==
{{Commons category}}
* Frédéric Beatrix, Peter Katzlinger: ''''. In: , online magazine (ISSN 1446-9723) published by the School of Mathematics and Statistics ]
* —]
* {{Springer|title=Duplication of the cube|id=p/d034200}}
* . J. J. O'Connor and E. F. Robertson in the MacTutor History of Mathematics archive.
* . Excerpt from '']'' by ].
* at ].
*

{{Algebraic numbers}}
{{Greek mathematics}}
{{Authority control}}

]
]
]
]
]

Latest revision as of 20:27, 18 December 2024

Ancient geometric construction problem
A unit cube (side = 1) and a cube with twice the volume (side = 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} = 1.2599210498948732... OEISA002580).

Doubling the cube, also known as the Delian problem, is an ancient geometric problem. Given the edge of a cube, the problem requires the construction of the edge of a second cube whose volume is double that of the first. As with the related problems of squaring the circle and trisecting the angle, doubling the cube is now known to be impossible to construct by using only a compass and straightedge, but even in ancient times solutions were known that employed other methods.

According to Eutocius, Archytas was the first to solve the problem of doubling the cube (the so-called Delian problem) with an ingenious geometric construction. The nonexistence of a compass-and-straightedge solution was finally proven by Pierre Wantzel in 1837.

In algebraic terms, doubling a unit cube requires the construction of a line segment of length x, where x = 2; in other words, x = 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} , the cube root of two. This is because a cube of side length 1 has a volume of 1 = 1, and a cube of twice that volume (a volume of 2) has a side length of the cube root of 2. The impossibility of doubling the cube is therefore equivalent to the statement that 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} is not a constructible number. This is a consequence of the fact that the coordinates of a new point constructed by a compass and straightedge are roots of polynomials over the field generated by the coordinates of previous points, of no greater degree than a quadratic. This implies that the degree of the field extension generated by a constructible point must be a power of 2. The field extension generated by 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} , however, is of degree 3.

Proof of impossibility

We begin with the unit line segment defined by points (0,0) and (1,0) in the plane. We are required to construct a line segment defined by two points separated by a distance of 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} . It is easily shown that compass and straightedge constructions would allow such a line segment to be freely moved to touch the origin, parallel with the unit line segment - so equivalently we may consider the task of constructing a line segment from (0,0) to ( 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} , 0), which entails constructing the point ( 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} , 0).

Respectively, the tools of a compass and straightedge allow us to create circles centred on one previously defined point and passing through another, and to create lines passing through two previously defined points. Any newly defined point either arises as the result of the intersection of two such circles, as the intersection of a circle and a line, or as the intersection of two lines. An exercise of elementary analytic geometry shows that in all three cases, both the x- and y-coordinates of the newly defined point satisfy a polynomial of degree no higher than a quadratic, with coefficients that are additions, subtractions, multiplications, and divisions involving the coordinates of the previously defined points (and rational numbers). Restated in more abstract terminology, the new x- and y-coordinates have minimal polynomials of degree at most 2 over the subfield of R {\displaystyle \mathbb {R} } generated by the previous coordinates. Therefore, the degree of the field extension corresponding to each new coordinate is 2 or 1.

So, given a coordinate of any constructed point, we may proceed inductively backwards through the x- and y-coordinates of the points in the order that they were defined until we reach the original pair of points (0,0) and (1,0). As every field extension has degree 2 or 1, and as the field extension over Q {\displaystyle \mathbb {Q} } of the coordinates of the original pair of points is clearly of degree 1, it follows from the tower rule that the degree of the field extension over Q {\displaystyle \mathbb {Q} } of any coordinate of a constructed point is a power of 2.

Now, p(x) = x − 2 = 0 is easily seen to be irreducible over Z {\displaystyle \mathbb {Z} } – any factorisation would involve a linear factor (xk) for some k Z {\displaystyle \mathbb {Z} } , and so k must be a root of p(x); but also k must divide 2 (by the rational root theorem); that is, k = 1, 2, −1 or −2, and none of these are roots of p(x). By Gauss's Lemma, p(x) is also irreducible over Q {\displaystyle \mathbb {Q} } , and is thus a minimal polynomial over Q {\displaystyle \mathbb {Q} } for 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} . The field extension Q ( 2 3 ) : Q {\displaystyle \mathbb {Q} ({\sqrt{2}}):\mathbb {Q} } is therefore of degree 3. But this is not a power of 2, so by the above:

  • 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} is not the coordinate of a constructible point, so
  • a line segment of 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} cannot be constructed with ruler and compass, and
  • the cube cannot be doubled using only a ruler and a compass.

History

The problem owes its name to a story concerning the citizens of Delos, who consulted the oracle at Delphi in order to learn how to defeat a plague sent by Apollo. According to Plutarch, however, the citizens of Delos consulted the oracle at Delphi to find a solution for their internal political problems at the time, which had intensified relationships among the citizens. The oracle responded that they must double the size of the altar to Apollo, which was a regular cube. The answer seemed strange to the Delians, and they consulted Plato, who was able to interpret the oracle as the mathematical problem of doubling the volume of a given cube, thus explaining the oracle as the advice of Apollo for the citizens of Delos to occupy themselves with the study of geometry and mathematics in order to calm down their passions.

According to Plutarch, Plato gave the problem to Eudoxus and Archytas and Menaechmus, who solved the problem using mechanical means, earning a rebuke from Plato for not solving the problem using pure geometry. This may be why the problem is referred to in the 350s BC by the author of the pseudo-Platonic Sisyphus (388e) as still unsolved. However another version of the story (attributed to Eratosthenes by Eutocius of Ascalon) says that all three found solutions but they were too abstract to be of practical value.

A significant development in finding a solution to the problem was the discovery by Hippocrates of Chios that it is equivalent to finding two geometric mean proportionals between a line segment and another with twice the length. In modern notation, this means that given segments of lengths a and 2a, the duplication of the cube is equivalent to finding segments of lengths r and s so that

a r = r s = s 2 a . {\displaystyle {\frac {a}{r}}={\frac {r}{s}}={\frac {s}{2a}}.}

In turn, this means that

r = a 2 3 . {\displaystyle r=a\cdot {\sqrt{2}}.}

But Pierre Wantzel proved in 1837 that the cube root of 2 is not constructible; that is, it cannot be constructed with straightedge and compass.

Solutions via means other than compass and straightedge

Menaechmus' original solution involves the intersection of two conic curves. Other more complicated methods of doubling the cube involve neusis, the cissoid of Diocles, the conchoid of Nicomedes, or the Philo line. Pandrosion, a probably female mathematician of ancient Greece, found a numerically accurate approximate solution using planes in three dimensions, but was heavily criticized by Pappus of Alexandria for not providing a proper mathematical proof. Archytas solved the problem in the 4th century BC using geometric construction in three dimensions, determining a certain point as the intersection of three surfaces of revolution.

Descartes theory of geometric solution of equations uses a parabola to introduce cubic equations, in this way it is possible to set up an equation whose solution is a cube root of two. Note that the parabola itself is not constructible except by three dimensional methods.

False claims of doubling the cube with compass and straightedge abound in mathematical crank literature (pseudomathematics).

Origami may also be used to construct the cube root of two by folding paper.

Using a marked ruler

There is a simple neusis construction using a marked ruler for a length which is the cube root of 2 times another length.

  1. Mark a ruler with the given length; this will eventually be GH.
  2. Construct an equilateral triangle ABC with the given length as side.
  3. Extend AB an equal amount again to D.
  4. Extend the line BC forming the line CE.
  5. Extend the line DC forming the line CF.
  6. Place the marked ruler so it goes through A and one end, G, of the marked length falls on ray CF and the other end of the marked length, H, falls on ray CE. Thus GH is the given length.

Then AG is the given length times 2 3 {\displaystyle {\sqrt{2}}} .

In music theory

In music theory, a natural analogue of doubling is the octave (a musical interval caused by doubling the frequency of a tone), and a natural analogue of a cube is dividing the octave into three parts, each the same interval. In this sense, the problem of doubling the cube is solved by the major third in equal temperament. This is a musical interval that is exactly one third of an octave. It multiplies the frequency of a tone by 2 4 / 12 = 2 1 / 3 = 2 3 {\displaystyle 2^{4/12}=2^{1/3}={\sqrt{2}}} , the side length of the Delian cube.

Explanatory notes

  1. The Delian problem shows up in Plato's Republic (c. 380 BC) VII.530

References

  1. ^ Kern, Willis F.; Bland, James R. (1934). Solid Mensuration With Proofs. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
  2. Menn, Stephen (2015). "How Archytas doubled the cube". In Holmes, Brooke; Fischer, Klaus-Dietrich (eds.). The Frontiers of Ancient Science: Essays in honor of Heinrich von Staden. Beiträge zur Altertumskunde. Vol. 338. De Gruyter. pp. 407–436. doi:10.1515/9783110336337-021.
  3. Masià, Ramon (2016). "A new reading of Archytas' doubling of the cube and its implications". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 70 (2): 175–204. doi:10.1007/s00407-015-0165-9. MR 3458183.
  4. Guilbeau, Lucye (1930). "The history of the solution of the cubic equation". Mathematics News Letter. 5 (4): 8–12. doi:10.2307/3027812. JSTOR 3027812.
  5. Zhmudʹ, Leonid I︠A︡kovlevich (2006). The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 84, quoting Plutarch and Theon of Smyrna. ISBN 978-3-11-017966-8.
  6. "Plutarch, De E apud Delphos, section 6 386.4". www.perseus.tufts.edu. Retrieved 2024-09-17.
  7. Plutarch, De genio Socratis 579.B
  8. (Plut., Quaestiones convivales VIII.ii, 718ef)
  9. Carl Werner Müller, Die Kurzdialoge der Appendix Platonica, Munich: Wilhelm Fink, 1975, pp. 105–106
  10. Knorr, Wilbur Richard (1986), The Ancient Tradition of Geometric Problems, Dover Books on Mathematics, Courier Dover Publications, p. 4, ISBN 9780486675329.
  11. T.L. Heath A History of Greek Mathematics, Vol. 1
  12. Lützen, Jesper (24 January 2010). "The Algebra of Geometric Impossibility: Descartes and Montucla on the Impossibility of the Duplication of the Cube and the Trisection of the Angle". Centaurus. 52 (1): 4–37. doi:10.1111/j.1600-0498.2009.00160.x.
  13. Knorr, Wilbur Richard (1989). "Pappus' texts on cube duplication". Textual Studies in Ancient and Medieval Geometry. Boston: Birkhäuser. pp. 63–76. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-3690-0_5. ISBN 9780817633875.
  14. Dörrie, Heinrich (1965). 100 Great Problems of Elementary Mathematics. Dover. p. 171. ISBN 0486-61348-8.
  15. Phillips, R. C. (October 1905), "The equal tempered scale", Musical Opinion and Music Trade Review, 29 (337): 41–42, ProQuest 7191936

External links

Algebraic numbers
icon Mathematics portal
Ancient Greek mathematics
Mathematicians
(timeline)
Treatises
Problems
Concepts
and definitions
Results
In Elements
Apollonius
Other
Centers
Related
History of
Other cultures
Ancient Greece portal • icon Mathematics portal
Categories:
Doubling the cube: Difference between revisions Add topic